Selected quad for the lemma: duty_n

Word A Word B Word C Word D Occurrence Frequency Band MI MI Band Prominent
duty_n bind_v law_n sin_n 1,412 5 5.0269 4 true
View all documents for the selected quad

Text snippets containing the quad

ID Title Author Corrected Date of Publication (TCP Date of Publication) STC Words Pages
A42237 The most excellent Hugo Grotius, his three books treating of the rights of war & peace in the first is handled, whether any war be just : in the second is shewed, the causes of war, both just and unjust : in the third is declared, what in war is lawful, that is, unpunishable : with the annotations digested into the body of every chapter / translated into English by William Evats ...; De jure belli et pacis. English Grotius, Hugo, 1583-1645.; Evats, William. 1682 (1682) Wing G2126; ESTC R8527 890,585 490

There are 20 snippets containing the selected quad. | View lemmatised text

patientia to take away thy Coat let him have thy Cloak also which words Cyprian thus expounds What is taken away from thee unjustly seek not to recover And so likewise Irenaeus Lib. 4. c. 2● If any man shall take away thy Coat do not grieve as if thou wert deprived of it against thy will but rather rejoyce as if thou hadst given it voluntarily And if any man shall compel thee to go with him a mile go with him not grudgingly but willingly not following him as a servant but going before him as a guide It is not every contest in Law that is therefore forbidden as St. Paul seems to interpret that place in 1 Cor. 6.4 5 6 7. But he forbids Christians to go to Law for every trifle or to convent their brethren before the Tribunals of the Heathen contrary to the custom of the Jews amongst whom it was a received opinion Qui adducit negotia Israelitica ad extraneos polluet nomen Dei He that makes a stranger Judge of any controversie between Israelites pollutes the name of God but Christ to exercise the patience of his disciples would not have them cavil in judgment for things easily recoverable as for a Coat or Cloak For though they might do it Optimo jure with the greatest Right yet was it much more acceptable to God rather to suffer such losses with patience than to prosecute the Law for them Apollonius Tyanaeus denies it to be the part of a wiseman to sue for a little money There is no judge saith Vlpian Philost 2 15. that can disapprove of that man who sets so little by his loss as not to vex himself for it with many sutes for that mans disposition that hates contention is no waies to be disallowed What Vlpian there saith is approved of by all good men and is no more than what Christ there commands collecting the sum and substance of his precepts out of these things that are most honest and vertuous But yet thou canst not hence well conclude that for a Parent or a Tutor to defend or recover by Law that which his Child or Pupil hath been wrongfully deprived of and without which he cannot subsist being thereunto compelled is any violation of this precept of Christ For it is one thing to contend for a Coat which haply we may spare and another thing to contend for that without which we cannot live In the Constitutions of Clement it is said concerning a Christian If he have a sute at Law let him endeavour as soon as he can to end it though it be to his loss What therefore is usually said of moral duties may also be said of these precepts that they consist not in a point like the negative precepts of the Law from which we cannot deviate in the least without sin for these have their huc usque their certain Latitudes wherein we may walk safely So in that precept that follows If any man shall compel thee to go with him a mile go with him two He saith not For trifles it is better to suffer than to ●ontend he that compels thee to go with him one hundred miles this had been hard because haply it would draw us too far from our own necessary concernments and so the injury or damage done would be greater to our selves than the benefit to him But he mentions a mile or two only which cannot much endamage us The sense of the words then must needs be this In such things as are not very damageable to our selves we are not too strictly to insist upon our own right but rather to grant more than is required from us that our patience and readiness to do good may be known unto all Thus Justin Martyr expounds these words What Christ there said tends only to this that we should behave our selves towards all men patiently obligingly and not prone to anger But it sollows Give unto him that asks and from him that would borrow turn not away Than which words if not understood with some limitation nothing sound harsher He that takes no care for his Family saith St. Paul is worse than an Infidel Let St. Paul himself be Judge who was best able to expound his Masters Law and who exhorting the Corinthians to extend their liberality to the poor at Jerusalem saith Not that others should be eased and you burdened but that by an equality your abundance should supply their wants that is to borrow the words of Livy in a case not unlike to this that out of your store ye may relieve the necessities of others Dabo egenti sed ipse non egeam I will give to the poor but so as that thereby I make not my self poor saith Seneca So also Chrysostom God requires those things of us that are in our power to give According to what a man hath saith St. Paul and not according to what a man hath not And he commends the Thessalonians that they gave above what they were able but yet he doth not exact the same from the Achaians To the like purpose is that of Cyrus in Xenophon What I find superabundant in mine own estate will be sufficient to relieve the wants of my friends By all which we may conclude The indulgence of the Hebrew Law That this precept of our Saviours as all the rest which follow in this Chapter are to be understood with some equitable limitation and not barely as the words import The Hebrew law to prevent the cruelty of Husbands to their Wives did indulge unto them the liberty of Divorce and to prevent private revenge whereunto that Nation was too much addicted gave liberty to the injured person to avenge himself not by his own hand but by requiring it from the Judges according to the Rule of Retaliation which Law was so pleasing to the Romans Which Christ reforms that they inserted it among those in the 12 Tables Si membrum rupit talio esto He that breaks a limb shall suffer the like But Christ being Master of much more patience was so far from approving this Law that he would not permit his disciples to repel some injuries either by force or judgment But what injuries were these Surely such as might easily be born not that patience was not commendable even in the greatest but that he was content with somewhat a more limited patience And therefore he instanceth only in a box on the Ear which neither endangers ●se nor limb but implyes only a slighting or contemning of us which doth not at all damnifie us Seneca in his Book entituled Of a wise mans Constancy distinguisheth between an injury and a reproach The former saith he is naturally more grievous the latter more light and to such only as are nicely bred troublesome Qua non laeduntur sed offenduntur whereby they are offended but not hurt Such is the weakness and vanity of mens minds that they esteem nothing worse than a reproach so we may find some
an Intestate to whom it naturally descends Dominion being once introduced that which naturally guides the Succession to the estate of a person dying intestate setting aside the Civil Law is our conjecture at the Will of the deceased For seeing that the force of Dominion is such that it may be transferred at the will of the right owner unto another Therefore in case a man dyes possest of an estate leaving nothing to testifie his mind after his death because it is not credible that he would leave it to him that could next catch it therefore shall it succeed to him to whom it is probable he would have left it had he lived to have declared it Defunctorum voluntatem intellexisse pro jure est saith Pliny Junior To have understood the Will of the deceased is sufficient to create a Right Now to the dead this favour is indulged That in cases that are doubtful it is presumed That every man would do that which is most just and honest whereof in the first place is the payment of his just debts and in the next that which though not due yet is most agreeable to our duty And therefore what is committed to a mans trust may be restored saith Paulus the person dying Intestate that trusted it to those that succeed him because it may be believed That his Will was freely to leave the lawful Inheritance unto them IV. Whether Parents do owe unto their Children any part of their goods It is much controverted by Lawyers Whether Parents may be said to owe their children Aliment Some of them hold it to be agreeable to Natural Reason but deny it to be a Debt But we think it fit here to distinguish of the word Debt which may be taken either strictly for that which by Commutative Justice we are obliged to do or largely for that which cannot with honour or honesty be left undone as being a duty arising from another spring but not from that of Justice First Reason Now Aliment is due to Children if Humane Laws do not otherwise determine of it in this looser sense In which I conceive that of Val. Maximus is to be understood Our Parents by nourishing us h●ve laid this obligation upon us to nourish our Children And that also of Plutarch in that most elegant Oration of his concerning the Love of Parents towards their Children Liberi haereditatem ut sibi debitam expectant Our Children look for our estates as due unto them after our death So great was the Equity of this Lib. 2. de vita cler ser 52. ad frat in eremo Gratian. c. 13. q. 2. c. 17. q. 4. in fine Pers l. 1. Second Reason That St. Augustine would not admit that the goods of such as had exheredated their own Children should be received by the Church And as Procopius in his Persian Wars observes Though Humane Laws do in other things extreamly differ one from another yet all Nations as well Romans as Barbarians in this agree That Children should succeed to their Parents as the right owners of what they leave Again Qui formam dat dat quae ad formam sunt necessaria He that gives the form gives things necessary to that form saith Aristotle Therefore he that gives man his existence ought as much as in him lies to provide for him all things necessary for a Natural and Social life for hereunto he was born There needs no Law to bind us to this duty for all other creatures even by Natures instinct do feed their young As Pliny observes of Swallows That with great equity they feed their little ones by turns Summa aequitate alternant cibum Hence it is that the Ancient Civilians do refer the Education of Children to the Law of Nature And Euripides comprehends all Creatures under one and the same Law Which saith he is common as well to men among themselves as to them with all other sensible Creatures For that which Natural Instinct commends to them the same doth Reason prescribe unto us Of such force is Natural affection that it easily perswades us to nourish our Children saith Justinian Nature is an Indulgent Mistress to all living creatures equally instructing them how to conserve not only themselves but those that are born of them that so by this successive Charity she may aspire to make her self immortal Quintilian brings in the Son claiming a Portion of his Fathers Estate by the Law of Nations Partem jure gentium p●to And Salust condemns that Testament as impious and unnatural by which the Son is excluded from his part of the Inheritance And because this is a debt that we owe to Nature therefore is the Mother bound to nourish the Child that hath no certain Father The Roman Laws made no provision for Bastards And though the Roman Laws made no provision for Children ex damnato legibus Concubitu that were illegitimate and that by Solons Laws it was provided That no man should leave any thing to his Natural Issue yet do the Canons of our Religion correct the severity of these Laws by teaching us That our Children however begotten by us should be a part of our care and that in case it be needful Beyond necessaries no man bound to provide for them we ought to leave them enough to preserve that life which we gave them but beyond necessaries is no man bound by the Law of Nature to provide for them Neither are we bound to nourish our Sons only but those also that proceed from them yea even to the third generation according to Justinian and that for humanity sake Neither should our Charity rest here but it should extend it self even unto those who issue out of our Loins and are born unto us by strange women if they cannot otherwise be maintained V. In Succession the Children of the deceased are to be preferred before their Parents and why Children ought also to nourish their Parents not only in obedience to many wholsome Laws but in common gratitude like the Storks who when their Parents are spent with age feed them and being faint receive them on their backs and carry them from place to place And therefore in fostering those who when we were Children fostered us we are Proverbially said To imitate the Stork † 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 Reverence to Parents and sustenance to Children Nic. 8. Solon is highly commended for setting a brand of infamy upon those that did it not Yet is not this so ordinary as that which we have said of Children Because Children when they are born bring nothing into the world with them whereby to live and have probably a longer time to live here than their Parents have And as honour and obedience is properly due to Parents and not to Children So is Sustentation due rather to Children than to Parents And thus is Lucian to be understood when he tells us That it is more agreeable to the dictates of Nature for
have promised But to clear this yet better we must carefully distinguish between the three degrees of speaking concerning things to come which either are or at least are reputed to be hereafter in our own power II. 1. That a bare assertion obligeth not The first consists in a bare assertion of what we purpose for the future things thus standing and in the same mind we now are And hereunto it is required that we speak sincerely and without guile what at that present time we think But not with any resolution to continue in that thought if the face of things change or if other chances happen which though we then foresee not yet may otherwise incline us For the mind of man hath not only a Natural Power See Q. Elizabeth's dealing with the Hollander B. 2. c. 14. §. 12. but a Right and Freedome to alter its counsels and if there be any weakness or error in the change as it often happens that is not intrinsick to the change but to the matter in that we change from the better to the worse III. 2. A Promise though naturally obliging yet transfers no Right to another The Second degree is when the will confines it self for the time to come giving some sign whereby the necessity of its perseverance is sufficiently declared and this may be called a Pollicitation or a Promise which setting aside the Civil Law obligeth either absolutely or under some condition yet gives no peculiar Right to another For in many cases it happens that there may be an obligation within our selves when there is no Right given to another as may appear by those debts of mercy and gratitude whereunto we may refer those of Constancy and Fidelity and therefore no man can by the Law of Nature require the thing promised from the right owner by vertue of such a Pollicitation nor can the Promiser be compelled by that Law to perform what he hath so promised IV. 3. What that Promise is that gives a Right to another Thirdly When the Will to the confinement adds some outward sign whereby its consent to transfer its own proper Right to another is sufficiently declared Which is a compleat Promise as having the like effect to the alienation of a mans Property For it is the way to alienate a thing or at least the alienation of some part of our Liberty or Freedome Unto the former belongs our Promises to give unto the latter our Promises to do something And hereof the Scriptures do give us a notable example where they tell us That God himself who cannot be bound by any Law yet professeth it to be contrary to his own Nature not to perform what he promiseth Neh. 9.8 1 Cor. 1.19.10.13 Prov. 6.1 Heb. 6.17 18. From whence it is plain That to perform our Promises is a duty springing from the Nature of Immutable Justice which as it is in God so is it in some measure common to all such as have the use of right Reason Let us hear the opinion of Solomon in this case My Son if thou hast been surety for thy Friend thou hast given thy Faith to a stranger or as the Septuagint translate it to thine Enemy Thou art ensnared by the words of thy mouth Thou are taken and bound by thine own Speech Whereunto may be added that of Thales the Philosopher Stipulatus sponsio are such Promises as are made with solemnity Numb 30.4 5 6. Vox mea facta tua est Sponde noxa presto est Engage freely and thou art not far from harm And that also of Chilo Sponsioni non deest jactura Engagements are seldome made to loss Hence it is that the Jews term a Promise Vinculum A Bond which also in the Scriptures is compared to a Vow as if by Vows and Promises we did contract as it were with God himself From the same Root ariseth the Greek word 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 which likewise signifies a Promise namely from 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 which signifies To have or to hold Because he to whom any thing is promised doth hold fast and as it were bind the Promiser These things promis'd Connanus his Arguments are easily answered For what the Lawyers say De nudo pacto non oritur actio A bare Promise will bear no Action hath respect only to what was introduced by the Roman Laws which made Stipulation to be an infallible sign of a deliberate mind Paulus the Lawyer speaks very warily of such Promises Sent. lib. 2. tit 14. If saith he we make a bare Promise to pay use it avails nothing for among Roman Citizens no Action ariseth from a bare Promise The like Laws we grant to be in force among other Nations Quae lex ad id praestandum nos quod alicui promisimus De Promisso non Sponso jam non promittunt de te sed spondent Seneca Ep. 19. obligat What Law saith Seneca binds us to perform all our Promises Where he speaks of humane Laws and of rash and inconsiderate Promises But if we respect the Law of Nature only there may be other signs of a mind perfectly resolv'd besides that which the Romans introduced by Stipulation or if there be any other such like which the Civil Law requires to beget an Action But as to that Promise which is made rashly and without due consideration neither do we admit it to have any obliging power as Theophrastus hath well observ'd Yea and as to that which is deliberately done but not with a purpose thereby to transfer our own proper Right to another Rash Promises bind not we deny that from thence there ariseth Naturally a Right to any man to exact the performance of it Although we do acknowledge That from such a Promise there may arise an obligation not in honesty alone but in a moral necessity to do it And as to that of Cicero we shall treat hereafter when we shall discourse of the manner how Contracts are to be understood But now let us see what Conditions are required to make a Promise valid V. To make a Promise compleat the use of Reason is required in the Promiser And in the first place it is requisite that he that promiseth should be endued with Reason which renders the Promises of Mad-men Ideots and Infants void and of no force but the case of Minors is somewhat different For although they are believed to be but of weak judgement as Women also are yet neither is this weakness of Judgement lasting nor is it of it self sufficient to invalid their acts At what years a young man or woman arrives at the use of Reason cannot certainly be determined but must be guessed at either by their daily Actions or by the Customes of every Nation Among the Jews a young man after thirteen years of age might oblige himself by any solemn Promise he should make and a young woman after twelve But the Civil Laws upon better reason thought good to make void many
we have pawn'd our Faith to commit a Sin the best way to preserve our Faith is to break our Promise For that is not properly called Faith that engages us to do wickedly Wherefore take the Advice of Isidore In malis Promissis rescinde Fidem Gratian. in turpi voto muta decretum impia est Promissio quae scelere impletur Make no scruple of breaking that Oath that would bind thee to a dishonest or unjust action for that Promise must needs be wicked that cannot be fulfilled but by making thee wicked VII Nor that impede a greater moral good Yea though that which is promised upon Oath be not unlawful yet if it cannot be performed without the omission of something that is a greater moral good it loseth its binding faculty For we owe unto God our growth in goodness and we cannot abridge our selves of this liberty without sinning against him Some there are saith Philo of so harsh and unsociable a nature either as bearing hatred to all mankind or so enslaved to their own inordinate passions that they even strengthen themselves in their churlish humours by rash and inconsiderate Vows as namely That they will never admit such a man either to bed or board or that they will never do such a man good nor ever receive any thing from him till death St. Augustine being consulted with about one Hubaldus who to save his own life being threatened had bound himself by Oath to marry his own Concubine and to thrust his own Mother and Brethren out of doors and never to relieve them gives this resolution of the Case That as to his marriage with his Concubine whom he had long enjoyed his Oath was binding for that was no sin But as to his not relieving his Mother and Brethren it could not bind him For Qui non alit necat To deny them necessaries was no better than to kill them And no Oath can oblige to a sin so unnatural The Error of the Jews concerning Oaths See Godw. Jewish Ant. pag. 274. Such a kind of Oath was called among the Jews an Oath concerning beneficence or doing good The form whereof we have set down Mat. 15.5 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 That is By the gift upon the Altar thou shalt never receive any good from me Which Oath was always to be so understood as if some direful Execration were at the tail of it As So do God to me and more also if thou ever receive any good from me which Oath was among the Jews thought to be the most binding of any yea though it were against our own Parents Such corrupt Interpreters of the Law of God were the Jewish Doctors in those superstitious times Which Christ there confutes making no distinction between honouring our parents and relieving them as appears by comparing that of Matthew with the like in Mark and with 1 Tim. 5.3 17. and Numb 23.11 Yea though it be not made against our Parents but against others yet doth it not bind because it is a duty we owe unto God to do good unto all men which is altogether inconsistent with such an Oath VIII Nor to impossibilities To things manifestly impossible no Oath can oblige us IX If the impossibility be only for the present how the Oath obligeth But as to things that are for a certain time impossible or supposed at present to be so the obligatory power of that Oath hangs in suspense insomuch that he that swears suppositively ought to endeavour as far as in him lies to make that which he hath sworn possible X. The form of Oaths The forms of Oaths may be different but the substance of all are alike For all invoke God as a Witness or as an Avenger both which in him are one and the same For in calling him to Witness who hath a Power and a Right to punish we do but bespeak him to a Revenge due to our Perfidiousness And he that is omniscient is therefore an Avenger because a Witness What is to swear saith Ambrose to the Emperour Valentinian but to acknowledge that Divine Power which thou invokest to witness and defend thy truth Every Oath saith Plutarch ends in some Curse in case we Swear falsely Quaest Rom. And therefore the ancient forms of making and swearing Leagues was usually by killing of Sacrifices as appears Gen. 15.9 c. and by that of the Romans in Livy Tu Jupiter ita illum ferito ut ego hunc porcum And do thou O Jupiter destroy him that breaketh this league as I do this Hogg And in another place the Priest killing a Lamb Prays the Gods to kill him that violates that Oath as he doth that Lamb. So in Polybius and Festus we read If I knowingly deceive let God cast me away from him as I do this Stone XI Oaths not by God only but by others also in relation to God oblige It was the custom of the Ancients not only to swear by God but by other both things and persons thereby either wishing those creatures might be noxious unto them in case they sware falsely as when they sware by the Sun the Moon the Heavens the Earth c. or wishing they might be punished in them as when they sware by their Head by their Lives by their Children by their Prince c. Neither did the prophane and barbarous people only swear thus but the Jews themselves Philo the Jew among his Special Laws tells us That it is not fit for us upon every slight occasion to have recourse to the Creator and Preserver of all things And Homer's Interpreters do testifie the same of the ancient Grecians that they were not easily induced to swear by God Oaths by the Creatures oblige but by other things that were present as by the Scepter c. Thus Apollonius testifies of Socrates That he sware by such things Non ut per Deos sed ne per Deos Not as by Gods but lest he should swear by the Gods And this custom as Porphyry records was introduced by that Prince who was so famous for his Justice King Rhadamanth So did Joseph according to the custom of that Nation among whom he lived swear by the Life of Pharaoh Elisha by the Life of Elias and the Shunamite by the Life of Elisha 2 King 4.30 Cant. 2.7 Mat. 5. Neither doth our Saviour as some think declare such Oaths to be less lawful or less binding than those whereby God himself was invoked But observing that the Jews did not so regard such Oaths in an opinion haply not unlike to his who said Sceptrum non putat esse Deos That he did not believe the Scepter to be the Gods He shews that even these are true Oaths See Wisd 14.20 and as binding as those that are made in the name of the true God It was very well said of Vlpian He that swears by his own safety seems to swear by God because he hath respect to some Divine power that preserves
doth not declare his knowledge to the right Owner is guilty So also St Chrysostome Not only the perjured persons but they that knowing of it De Statuis 14. conceal the perjury are guilty They that contribute their counsel and advice for so runs the Attick Law He that gives his counsel to an act that is wicked is involved in the same punishment with him that doth it They that countenance encourage or commend a Malefactor so St Chrysostome Pejor peccante qui peccatum laudat He that praiseth and applauds a wicked act is more wicked than he that effects it And by the Law of the Lombards Qui facinorosum astans hortatur pro faciente habetur The By-stander that encourageth a Malefactor is equally to be punished with him They who having full power and authority to forbid and restrain Offenders do it not So thought St. Chrysostome Not they only that commit the theft but they also that did not hinder the commission of it when it was in their power to do it are in the same manner to be punished Just as he who hinders a wounded person from being cured is as guilty as he that wounds him even unto death So they who being strictly bound in Duty to help those that are oppressed and do it not And they who do not disswade when they ought to do it And lastly They that conceal the Fact which they are bound by some Law to make known All these are obnoxious to the same punishment if there be in them such a malignity of Spirit as may suffice to deserve punishment according to what we have already said in the preceding Chapter II. How Princes and States are punishable by reason of the facts of their Subjects This will be made clearer by examples Where offences are but personal there the punishment is not to be national No Community or other Civil Society of men may justly be punished for the fault of some particular persons without either committing or omitting some fact or duty of their own whereunto they were generally obliged For as St Augustine well observes In every Nation those sins which are committed by particular persons are to be distinguished from those that are done in common as when the whole Body of the people being assembled do unanimously decree it to be done Hence ariseth that Clause usual in all Leagues Si defexerit publico Consilio If any thing shall be done to the contrary by any publick Decree then shall the League be adjudged as broken Thus the Locrians in Livy excuse themselves to the Roman Senate saying That their defection proceeded from some ignorant and ill affected people and not by any publick Order of the Senate And the Rhodians in the same Senate make their defence by the same Argument distinguishing between the publick Acts of the City and the private Acts of some particular persons There is no City say they so well governed but may sometimes have some malignant Citizens sitting even at the Stern besides an unexperienced multitude always And if the attempts of every private person were ground sufficient for a just war no City could long subsist Thus St. Chrysostome likewise argues It was not the common crime of the City but of some strangers and Foreigners who do all things rather through rashness and ignorance of the Laws than by reason Neither saith he is it just that so great a City should be destroyed for the indiscretion of some few nor that the innocent should equally suffer with the nocent So neither are the sins of Children to be imputed to their Parents nor Masters to be punished for the crimes of their Servants nor others that govern for those whom they govern unless it be for some delinquency of their own Now of those ways or means whereby they that preside over others may be accessary to their sins and so involv'd in their punishments there are two of singular use and require our strictest disquisition As first By connivence 1. By Connivence For he that knows that such a crime will be committed which he can hinder and is bound to do it but doth it not is guilty of that crime when it is committed Thus Cicero argues this Case against Piso Cicero in Pisonem It is not much material saith he especial●y in a Consul whether he do himself stir up the people to sedition by his own pernicious Laws and wicked Speeches and so disturb the peace of the Commonwealth or whether by his connivence he permits others so to do Par est delinquere delinquentes non prohibere It is the same thing saith Agapetus to Justinian to be wicked our selves and to suffer others to be so when it lyes in our power to help it He that suffers a Sinner to sin saith Arnobius adds unto him the strength of confidence Of the same opinion was Salvian He who having a power to prohibit a wicked act and doth it not doth in effect command it And St. Augustine likewise He that doth not resist and oppose himself against a sin when he can do it seems to give his consent unto it By the Roman Laws if a Servant did kill a man with his Masters knowledge the main guilt was transferred to his Master as if he himself had been the Murtherer Even so he that suffers his Bond-slave to be prostituted when he might rescue her was by the same Law judged the Prostitutor By the Fabian Law if one Mans Servant with the consent of his Master seduced another mans Servant the Master of the Seducer was punished for it But as I said before it is requisite that besides the bare knowledg there be also a power and authority sufficient to restrain and hinder the committing of it And this is that which the Laws intend for when knowledge is commanded to be punished it is taken for connivence or toleration so that he stands guilty who having a power to forbid the doing of a wicked act doth it not And in this Case knowledg is taken for that which hath the consent of the will and so it is to be understood as if the fact were committed by his advice and counsel And therefore as the Master is not bound by his Servants crime though he do know thereof if that Servant shall contemn his Masters authority and proclaim himself a Freeman and as Parents are not bound by their Childrens crimes though they know of them if those Children are not under the power and tuition of their Parents because neither Masters nor Parents have any power and authority over them So on the other side although they had power and authority over them and so might thereby prohibit the doing of such crimes yet if they knew nothing of their purpose and intention to commit such acts they cannot be punished for them For both these must necessarily concur to make one man guilty of another mans crime knowledge of the sin committed and not restraining them when it was in
politick 377. not punishable for their Subjects crimes but for neglect of their own duty 393 394. their Oaths may strengthen their power not lessen their supremacy page 44 45 Kings vanquished what they had is the Conquerours 479. whether to be spared page 502 503 Kings warring for punishment bound to repair their Subjects loss page 420 Kings though conquered yet substituted under the Conquerour page 527 Kings should have a general care of humane Society page 388 The Contracts of Kings whether Laws and when page 177 The King a Minor Mad a Captive in whom the power to make Peace is page 544 A King not reigning by full Right his acts may be null'd by the Peoples Laws page 176 A King who pays not his Army is bound to satifie the wrongs done by it page 533 A King murthered nothing ensues but Blood and Slaughter page 65 A King may claim relief by the Laws against such private acts of his as are occasioned by fraud fear error and against extortion page 176 A good King respects what he ought to do not what he may do page 46 Kings of Persia absolute yet swear not to alter the Laws page 45 Kings falsifying their Oaths judged after death ibid. Kings of Israel punished beaten with Rods 47. in some cases had not Right to judge ibid. Kingly Government asserted by the Gospel page 18 Kingdoms absolute 38. mixt between Monarchy and Principality 47 48. Patrimonial if indivisible due to the eldest Son page 127 Kingdoms transfer'd by the People are inheritances yet separable from others nor lyable to Debts ibid. in what cases alienable not possest in full Right not alienable without the Peoples consent page 44. Kingdom and Principality promiscuously used page 41 Kingdoms transfer'd by the People if in doubt individual and to descend rather to Males than Females 128. more difficultly kept than conquered 526. how divided 143. some held during the Peoples pleasure 42. bounded some by natural some by artificial Bounds page 94 137 Kingdoms held by a Right usufructuary others by a full Right of Propriety and so alienable page 42 Kingdoms Patrimonial may descend to such as are nearest to the first King page 127 Kings absolute accountable to none 39. have a Right from God to command Subjects to obey 54. of Judah could not inflict capital Punishments but the Kings of Israel might unless in some cases page 63 Kings govern not only according to the Laws but the Laws themselves for the publick good page 38 39 Kings in their private concerns submit their cases to be judged by the Judges which they themselves make page 50 L. LAcedemonians prefer the Son born after the Father is King before him born before 132. they used more craft than force in their War 437. their custom concerning Lands taken page 410 Levinus his advice to the Roman Senate page 56 Lands taken in War are his that maintains it 472. when said to be gained 470. may be sold the measure named and yet not according to that measure page 137 Lands some divided and artificially fenced some assigned by measure and some arcifinious page 94 Lands if in doubt not judged arcifinious ibid. now found if prepossest no ground of War if drowned where presumed to be deserted page 137 Lands drowned naturally not lost ibid. gained by War several ways disposed yet always as the People ordered 472. recovered by Postliminy page 491 Humane Laws may ordain things preternatural but not things against nature page 81 89 A Lawmaker may take away the condemning power of the Law as to particular Acts or Persons page 376 377 Law what 4. of Nature what it is ibid. from whence Pref. v. in some sence the Law of God vi not alterable by God himself 5. distinguish'd into that which is so purely and that which is so for some certain States page 140 The Law of Moses taken in a twofold sence carnally and spiritually page 17 Law Ceremonial and Judicial when and how taken away 19. Mosaical hath neither first nor last page 110 The Law of Nature and Nations takes place where the Civil cannot be exercised page 368 The Law of Nature explained by those given by God Pref. vi The Law of Nature how proved and distinguished from others Pref. xiv nothing in the Old Law repugnant unto it xviii it hath sometimes some shew of change Pref. ix The Laws of Nature and Nations violated every Prince may make War page 384 Every man takes that to be the Law of Nature that it first imbibes page 385 The Law doth not always null what it for bids 37. of Tythes and the Sabbath how obliging Christians page 10 A Law implies every mans express conse●t 517. grounded upon presumption of a fact never done obligeth not page 152 153 The Laws of Holland for Lands drowned page 137 The Roman Law concerning such Contracts wherein the inequality is above half the value page 160 161 The Law in permitting a private man to kill a Thief whether it frees the conscience page 76 373 374 The Civil Law may forbid what naturally is Lawful page 81 The Law of Vsucapion whether it extends to the Supreme Power 101. or to its parts ibid. The universal reason of the Law particularly failing in any one fact the Law may be dispensed with page 153 377 How far a Law-maker obligeth himself page 377 c. Hebrew Laws forbidding Polygamy and Divorce page 105 106 What Laws oblige page 530 The Hebrew Laws Copies for Christians except in three Cases page 10 Laws and Contracts how they differ 178. not all obliging 178 179. common Agreements amongst the People 150 151. some very unjust page 121 Laws adjudging Criminals to death to be favourably interpreted 59. the Divine Laws judging to death have sometimes tacite exceptions ibid. Laws respect that which is generally profitable 56. some may be made decreeing when and how the Supreme shall be lost page 101 Laws concerning things promised oblige 152. judging to death the Relations of criminal Malefactors unjust page 403 Law Civil concerning the promises of Minors page 152 Laws pinnacle the hand Philosophy the mind 160. respect not small cheats and why ibid. diverse concerning buying and selling page 161 Law Divine voluntary how different from the Law of Nature 7. it obliged before it was written 8. Civil what 7. whence Pref. vii Ceremonial when abrogated and the Judicial when page 9 Laws given to the Jews oblige not Strangers 8. to the Mos cal Law the Israelites only stood obliged but to that of Circumcision all Abraham's Posterity page 9 Laws have two Parts directive to Kings and coercive to Subjects page 39 Laws given by God three times to Adam Noah Christ 8. the Old not useless by the coming of the New Pref. xviii Laws should command things possible 375. give testimony of their integrity page 430 Laws differ from counsels and how 3 4. and from permission and how page 4. A Law made against Murtherers by Force and Armes judgeth all
them will quickly find the consequences to be inconsistent with Government when being disarmed they shall be disabled to defend themselves against their Neighbours to suppress mutinies and seditions at home or to give that protection unto their own subjects against rapine and violence which in honour and Conscience is due unto them But let these suffice to dissolve those objections that are usually brought out of holy Writ against the lawfulness of War and now let us see what may be brought to confirm our opinion namely That all War is not unlawful And here in the first place we may alledge many Authors and those more antient Arguments proving some Wars lawful who hold That Christians may lawfuly put to death incorrigible Malefactors and consequently may make a just War of which Clemens Alexandrinus shall lead the van A Christian saith he being called to be a Supream Magistrate as was Moses is to be unto his Subjects a living Law encouraging the just with rewards and restraining the unjust by severe punishments And in another place describing the habit of a Christian he saith Invitis pedibus That it would become him to be unshod unless he be a Souldier In those Constitutions that are fathered upon Clemens Romanus we read That every putting of men to death is not unlawful but that only which destroys an innocent person yet so notwithstanding that the Magistrate alone is to determin who are innocent But setting aside these private authorities let us proceed to those that are publick that is of the Church which in this case is of greatest moment And this I affirm That no man was ever rejected from Baptism or Excommunicated the Church because he was a Souldier which certainly ought to have been done had War been in consistent with the precepts of the new Law Const l. 8. c. 32. The same Author elsewhere sets down who anciently were to be admitted to and who were to be rejected from Baptism Let the Souldier saith he that desires Baptism be instructed to abstain from wrong doing and from oppression and to content himself with his pay If he be willing to obey let him be admitted Tertullian in his Apology speaking in the person of Christians saith Navigamus nos vobiscum militamus We both sail and fight together with you in the same Fleet. A little before he had said We though strangers do notwithstanding supply all your places and Offices we fill your Cities Islands Castles Towns Councils yea and your very Camps And in the same book he tells the Emperour M. Aurelius That the prayers of his Christian Souldiers had procured from God Rain in the time of Drought And in his book De Corona he commends the Gallantry and Magnanimity of that Souldier before all his brethren that had thrown away the Garland when he had won it intimating unto the said Emperor that he had many other such Christian Souldiers Whereunto we may add That some Souldiers there were that endured Torments even to death for the Christian Faith and were therefore worthily admitted by the Church to the same honour with other Martyrs amongst whom he makes mention of three of Pauls Companions one Cerealis under Decian Marinus under the Emperor Valerian 50 Souldiers under Aurelian Victor Maurus and Valentinus with diverse others Cyprian concerning Laurentinus and Ignatius both African Souldiers writes thus They were once Souldiers fighting under secular Princes but they were also true Souldiers of God when by the confession of their faith in Christ they vanquished the Devil and by their invincible patience under the Cross were ennobled with the Crown of Martyrdom Whereby it is plain what esteem the Primitive Christians had of Souldiers even before any of their Emperors under whom they served became Christians And if the Christians of those times did express an unwillingness to be spectators at the execution of Capital punishments it is not to be wondred at considering that those punishments were but too frequently executed upon their fellow Christians especially if we add thereunto some grains of allowance for that the Roman Laws were far more severe and cruel than would consist with Christian Lenity As sufficiently appears by that one Silanian Decree of the Senate the Rigor whereof was somewhat mitigated by the Emperor Adrian as Spartianus Spartianus records it Amongst which severe Laws we may place that which forbad the Testimony of any servant to be taken unless he were tortured But after that Constantine the Great began not only to approve of but to advance Christianity even then also were Capital punishments frequently executed For even Constantine himself amongst many others enacted this Law of sowing up of Paracides Paracides in a sack which is yet extant in the Code under the Title of Murtherers of their own Parents or Children though he was otherwise so remiss in punishing that by several Historians it was imputed unto him as a Blemish Yet Zonaras gives this Testimony of him That he was very merciful to such as reformed their evil lives for he would often say Abscindendum est membrum aegrotans ac putridum ne sana contagio corrumpat non id quod aut sanatum jam sit aut sanescat That member that is putrid and incurable is to be cut off lest the sound should be infected but not that which is either healed or healing Besides Constantine had a multitude of Christians in his Army and as Historians tell us had the name of Christ embroydered on his Banners and from him it was that the Military Oath was changed into that form extant in Vigetius namely By God by Christ and the Holy Ghost and by the Majesty of the Emperor who according to Gods Ordinance is to be beloved and reverenced by all mankind Neither was there at that time any one Bishop that we read of among so many that were great sufferers for Religion that did ever reprove Constantine for putting Malefactors to death or for making of War or that did upon the account of Religion deterr Souldiers from their Military duties though many of them were severe Disciplinarians sparing neither Prince nor people that were defective in their duties Such was in the Reign of Theodosius the Emperor St. Ambrose Serm. 7. who thus declares his opinion concerning War Non Militare Delictum est sed propter praedam Militare Simply to go to War is no sin but to fight for spoil and plunder is wicked So likewise in his Offices That force whereby either our Country is defended from our enemies by War or the weak and innocent defended at home or our Associates from Pirats and Robbers is perfect Justice This Argument is of so great force that I shall need no other And yet I am not ignorant that sometimes Bishops and other good Christians have often by their Intercession turned Capital punishments into Pecuniary Mulcts or some lesser punishments not reaching to life Officium sacerdotis est intervenire pro
the very same words But yet if either for this or for any other cause any injury be offered unto us because it so please him that hath the Soveraign Power it ought rather to be patiently tolerated than by force resisted For although we do not owe an active obedience to such Commands of Princes yet we do owe a passive though we ought not to violate the laws of God or of Nature to fulfil the will of the greatest Monarch yet ought we rather patiently to submit to whatsoever he shall inflict upon us for not obeying than by resistance to violate our Countries peace The best and safest course we can steer in such a case is either by Flight to preserve our selves or resolvedly to undergo whatsoever shall be imposed on us II. War against Superiors as such unlawful And naturally all men have a right to repel Injuries from themselves by resisting them as we have already said But Civil Societies being once instituted for the preservation of Peace there presently succeeded unto that Common-wealth a certain greater Right over us and ours so far forth as was necessary for that end And therefore that promiscuous Right that Nature gave us to resist the Common-wealth for the maintaining of good order and the publick peace hath a right to prohibit which without all doubt it doth seeing that otherwise it cannot obtain the end it proposeth to it self For in case that promiscuous Right of forceable resistance should be tolerated it would be no longer a Common-wealth that is a Sanctuary against Oppression but a confused Rabble such as that of the Cyclops whereof the Poet thus Where every Ass May on his Wife and Children Judgment pass A dissolute Company where all are speakers and no hearers Like unto that which Valerius records of the Bebricii Who all Leagues and Laws disdain And Justice which mens minds in peace retain Salust makes mention of a wild and savage people living like Beasts in Woods and Mountains without Laws and without Government whom he calls Aborigines And in another place of the Getuli who had neither Laws good Customs nor any Princes to govern them But Cities cannot subsist without these Generale pactum est societatis humanae regibus obedire All humane Societies saith St. Augustine unanimously agree in this to obey Kings So Aeschylus Kings live by their own Laws subject to none And Sophocles They Princes are obey we must what not To the same Tune sings Euripides Folly in Kings must be with patience born Whereunto agrees that of Tacitus Principi summum rerum arbitrium Dii dederunt c. Subditis obsequii gloria relicta est God hath invested a Prince with Soveraign Power leaving nothing to Subjects but the glory of Obedience And here also Sen. Things base seem Noble when by Princes done What they Impose bear thou be 't right or wrong Wherewith agrees that of Salust Impunè quid vis facere hoc est Regem esse To do anything without fear of punishment is peculiar to Kings for as Mark Anthony urged in Herod's case If he were accountable for what he hath done as a King he could not be a King Hence it is that the Majesty of such as have Soveraign Power whether in one or more is senced with so many and so severe Laws and the licentiousness of Subjects restrained with such sharp and exquisite torments which were unreasonable if to resist them were lawful If a Souldier resist his Captain that strikes him An Officer striking must not be struck again and but lay hold on his Partisan he shall be cashiered but if he either break it or offer to strike again he shall be put to death for as Aristotle observes If he that is an Officer strike he shall not be struck again III. The unlawfulness of making war against our Superiors proved by the Jewish Law By the Hebrew Law He that behaved himself contumaciously against either the High-Priest or against him who was extraordinarily by God ordained to govern his people was to be put to death and that which in the eighth Chapter of the first Book of Samuel is spoken of the right of Kings to him that throughly inspects it is neither to be understood of their true and just rights that is of what they may do justly and honestly for the duty of Kings is much otherwise described Deut. 8.11 nor is it to be understood barely of what he will do for then it had signified nothing that was singular or extraordinary Jos 1.18 1 Sam. 8.11 Deut. 17.14 for private men do the same to private men But it is to be understood of such a fact as usurps or carries with it the priviledge of what is right that is that it must not be resisted although it be not right for Kings have a Right peculiar to themselves and what in others is punishable in them is not That old Saying Summum jus summa injuria Extreme right is extreme wrong is best fitted to the case of Kings whose absolute power mak●s that seem right which strictly taken is not so There is a main difference between Right in this sence taken Right differenced from Just and Just for in the former sence it comprehends whatsoever may be done without fear of punishment but Just respects only things lawful and honest And though some Kings there be who are what Servius in Cicero's Philippicks is commanded to be magis Justitiae quam Juris Consulti More regardful of their honour and duty than of their power and prerogatives Yet this doth not diminish their Soveraign Right because if they will they may do otherwise without the danger of being resisted And therefore it is added in that place of Samuel before cited That when the people should at any time be thus oppressed by their Kings as if there were no remedy to be expected from men they should invoke his help who is the Supream Judge of the whole Earth So that whatsoever a King doth though the same done by an inferiour person would be an Injury yet being done by him is Right As a Judge is said Jus reddere to do right though the sentence he gives be unrighteous IV. By the Gospel Law When Christ in the New Testament commanded to give Caesar his due doubtless he intended that his Disciples should yield as great if not a greater obedience as well active as passive unto the higher Power than what was due from the Jews to their Kings which St. Paul who was best able to Interpret his Masters words expounding Rom. 13. doth at large describe the duty of Subjects Rom. 13.2 charging those that resist the power of Kings with no less Crime than Rebellion against Gods Ordinance and with a Judgement as great as their sin For saith he They that do so resist shall receive unto themselves damnation And a little after he urgeth the necessity of our subjection Not altogether for fear but for Conscience as knowing that He
King though wicked for certainly he by whose Providence all Kings reign will pursue the Regicide with vengeance inevitably To reproach any private man falsly is forbidden by the Law but of a King Kings must not be reviled much less killed though wicked we must not speak evil though he deserve it because as he that wrote the Problems fathered upon Aristotle saith He that speaketh evil of the Governor scandalizeth the whole City So Joab concludes concerning Shimei as Josephus testifies Shalt thou not dye who presumest to curse him whom God hath placed in the Throne of the Kingdom The Laws saith Julian are very severe on the behalf of Princes for he that is injurious unto them doth wilfully trample upon the Laws themselves Misopogoris Now if we must not speak evil of Kings much less must we do evil against them David repented but for offering violence to Saul's Garments so great was the Reverence that he bare to his Person and deservedly for since their Soveraign Power cannot but expose them to the general hatred therefore it is fit that their security should especially be provided for This saith Quintilian is the fate of such as sit at the Stern of Government that they cannot discharge their duty faithfully nor provide for the publick safety without the envy of many The Laws are severe in the defence of Kings And for this cause are the persons of Kings guarded with such severe Laws which seem like Draco's to be wrote in blood As may appear by those enacted by the Romans for the security of their Tribunes whereby their persons became inviolable Amongst other wise Sayings of the Esseni this was one That the persons of Kings should be held as sacred And that of Homer was as notable His chiefest care was for the King That nothing should endanger him And no marvel For as St. Chrysostom well observes If any man kill a Sheep 1 Tim. 1. And why he but lessens the number of them but if he kill the Shepherd he dissipates the whole Flock The very name of a King as Curtius tells us among such Nations as were Governed by Kings was as venerable as that of God So Artabanus the Persian Plut. Them Amongst many and those most excellent Laws we have this seems to be the best which commands us to adore our Kings as the very Image of God who is the Saviour of all And therefore as Plutarch speaks Nec fas nec licitum est Regis corpori manus inferre It is not permitted by the Laws of God or Man to offer violence to the person of a King But as the same Plutarch in another place tells us The principal part of valour is to save him that saves all If the Eye observe a blow threatning the Head the Hand being instructed by Nature interposeth it self as preferring the safety of the Head whereupon all the other members depend before their own Wherefore as Cassiodore notes De Amicitia He that with the loss of his own life redeems the life of his Prince doth well We are to prefer his life before our own if in so doing he propose to himself the freeing of his own soul rather than that of another mans body for as Conscience teacheth him to express his fidelity to his Soveraign so doth right reason instruct him to prefer the life of his Prince before the safety of his own body But here a more difficult question ariseth as namely whether what was lawful for David and the Maccabees Whether Davids example and the Maccabees be sufficient to justifie Christians in like cases 1 Pet. 4.12 13 14 15 16. Christs advice is to flee where the duties of our calling will permit but beyond that nothing be likewise lawful for us Christians Or whether Christ who so often enjoyns us to take up our Cross do not require from us a greater measure of patience Surely where our Superiors threaten us with death upon the account of Religion our Saviour advised such as are not obliged by the necessary duties of their calling to reside in any one place to flee but beyond this nothing St. Peter tells us That Christ in suffering left us an ensample who though he knew no sin nor had any guile found in his mouth yet being reviled he reviled not again when he suffered he threatned not but remitted his cause to him that judgeth righteously Nay he adviseth us to give thanks unto God and to rejoyce when we suffer persecution for our Religion And we may read how mightily Christian Religion hath grown and been advanced by this admirable gift of patience wherefore how injurious to those ancient Christians who living in or near the times of either the Apostles themselves or men truly Apostolical must needs be well instructed in their Discipline and consequently walked more exactly according to their rules yet suffered death for their Faith how injurious I say to these men are they who hold that they wanted not a will to resist but rather a power to defend themselves at the approach of death Surely Tertullian had never been so imprudent nay impudent as so confidently to have affirmed such an untruth So Tertullian whereof he knew the Emperor could not be ignorant when he wrote thus unto him If we had a will to take our private revenge or to act as publick Enemies could we want either numbers of Men or stores of warlike Provisions Are the Moors Germans Parthians or the People of any one Nation more than those of the whole World We though Strangers yet do fill all places in your Dominions your Cities Islands Castles Forts Assemblies your very Camps Tribes Courts Palaces Senates only your Temples we leave to your selves For what war have not we always declared our selves fit and ready though in numbers of men we have sometimes been very unequal How cometh it then to pass that we suffer death so meekly so patiently but that we are instructed by our Religion that it is much better to be killed than to kill Cyprian also treading in his Masters steps openly declares That it was from the Principles of their Religion that Christians being apprehended made no resistance nor attempted any revenge for injuries unjustly done them though they wanted neither numbers of men nor other means to have resisted But it was their confidence of some Divine Vengeance that would fall upon their Persecutors that made them thus patient Lib. 5. and that perswaded the Innocent to give way to the Nocent So Lactantius We are willing to confide in the Majesty of God who is able as well to revenge the contempt done to himself as the injuries and hardships done unto us Wherefore though our sufferings be such as cannot be exprest yet do we not mutter a word of discontent but refer our selves wholly to him who judgeth righteously Lib. 6. Qu. 10. in Joshua And to the same Tune sings St. Augustin When Princes err they
si alitus sit ferendus est Either not to nourish a Lion or being nourisht not to provoke him It is indeed a very difficult case and will admit of a strong debate Whether Peace or liberty be most acceptable Whether Peace or Liberty be most eligible Cicero makes this question the most difficult of all others in the Politicks to be resolved Whether our Countrey being opprest by Tyranny we may attempt to redeem it although with the danger of its desolation But it is not for private men to determine what the Common Judgement of the people would be in this case but this we abominate as being grosly unjust to make our Countries Liberty a cloak for our own Ambition and to pretend to deliver her when we intend to inslave her Sylla being demanded App. Civit. 1. Why he marcht into his own Countrey so strongly Armed answered Vt eam à Tyrannis liberem To deliver it from Tyrants When he that pretended so to do was himself the greatest Tyrant Plut. Catent Major So Antiochus brought a Mighty Army into Greece alledging that he came to set Greece at Liberty when indeed it wanted none His pretence was Liberty but his Intent Tyranny Crudelitatem Damnat crudelitatem init By condemning Tyranny he trapans them into it Cicero Ep. Fam. l. 1. No alterations of Government without violent commotions It was much better Counsel that Plato gave to Perdiccas which Plato thus renders That he should attempt no more in the Common-wealth than he could justifie to his Subjects For that nothing savouring of force or violence should be obtruded upon either our Parents or our Countrey To the same sense is that of Salust Though thou couldst govern thy Countrey or thy Parents by force and correct at thy pleasure every small offence yet would it seem harsh and troublesome especially considering that no violent thing can be permanent Bello Jug nor any Mutations of Government without violent Commotions War Rapine and such like acts of hostility Not much different from this is that of Statius in Plutarch Vita Brut. It becomes not a wise or a prudent man to endanger himself in Popular Tumults amongst either Fools or Knaves Whereunto we may also not impertinently refer that of St. Ambrose To deliver the poor from oppression so it be without raising Tumults or Sedition is commendable This also will highly advance thy Credit and Reputation if thou canst rescue the poor out of the hands of the Oppressors and deliver him that is wrongfully condemned to dye so that thou do it without raising Tumults or moving Sedition Lest otherwise thou shouldst seem to do it rather out of an affectation of Popularity and Vain glory than out of Pity and Commiseration and so consequently make those wounds deeper which thou shouldest heal It was the opinion of Aquinas That the pulling down of Government though Tyrannical was sometimes Seditious Neither are we much moved to the contrary by that fact of Ehud to Eglon King of the Moabites For the Scriptures plainly tell us Judg. 3.15 That God raised up Ehud to deliver Israel What Ehud did was done by the special Warrant of God himself Neither doth it appear That this King of the Moabites had by Agreement no right of Soveraignty Nehem. 9.27 For God we read did execute his Judgements even against other Kings by such Instruments as he himself was pleased to raise up to that purpose as may be collected by Jehu against Joram 2 Kin. 9. XX. No private man to be Judge in this case But it is especially to be noted That no private person ought to determine Controversies of this nature but should rather obey the present possessor As Christ commanded to pay Tribute to Caesar † Mat. 22.20 because his Image made the Money currant which was a convincing argument that he was in full possession of the Empire at that time For the Coining of Money was ever the most certain sign of the Possession of the Empire CHAP. V. Who may lawfully make War I. The Efficient Causes of War are either the Principals in their own cause II. Or in the Cause of another III. Or Instrumental as Servants and Subjects IV. By the Law of Nature none are prohibited from War I. The principal efficient Cause AS in all other things so in Actions that are voluntary there are three sorts of Causes efficient that is to say Principal Auxiliary and Instrumental The Principal efficient cause in a War is for the most part he whose the quarrel is In a private War any private person In a publick he that hath the publick Power especially if it be Supreme Whether a War may be justly undertaken in the behalf of another not making War shall be discust hereafter In the mean time this is most certain That naturally every man hath a Right to revenge his own quarrel and for this cause were hands given unto us II. Auxiliary Neither have we a Right to vindicate our own quarrels only but we may both lawfully and laudably improve our Right to the vindication of other mens also They that treat of Offices say truly Nihil utilius homini homine altero That there is nothing so usuful and profitable unto man as another man There are several obligations wherein we stand bound to one another for mutual help and assistance For kinsmen do usually combine to help one another So one Neighbour being opprest invokes the help of another So also do Citizens the aid of their fellow-Citizens Aristotle thought it a duty incumbent to every man to assume Arms either to defend himself in case an injury were offered him or to assist his Kinsmen his Benefactors or his Companions in cases of oppression And in Solon's esteem That was the best Common-wealth wherein every man was as sensible of Injuries offered to another It was well said of Menander as if they had been offered to themselves ●●juriarum si Improbis Auctoribus Reponeremus ultionem singuli N●b● pu●antes fieri quod sit alteri Inter nos juncti Conspiratis viribus Non praevaleret Innocentiae Impetus Audax Malorum Qui custoditi undique Jussique poenas quas merentur pe●●●e Aut nulli penitus essent aut pa●ci admodum Hence is that of Plautus Praetorquete Injuriae prius Collum quam ad vos perveniat Break the Neck of an Injury before it comes at us But though all other obligations should fail yet it is sufficient that we are linkt together in the common stock of humanity For ab homine nihil humani alienum Nothing that is incident to humane nature should be to any man strange Democritus tells us That it is a duty incumbent upon every man so far as he is able to succour all that are oppressed with wrong and not at all to neglect it For this saith he is both just and honest Which Lactantius thus expresseth God saith he who denyed to all
notwithstanding the children do naturally owe reverence could not by her descent make the Marriage void no nor the father of a Free-man And if the Father himself be under the power of his own Father then the consents of both Father and Grand-father are required to the Sons Marriage But to the Marriage of a Daughter the Grand-fathers consent alone sufficeth Which differences being altogether unknown to the Law of Nature doth evidently prove that they arise not from the Natural but from the Civil Laws We find in Sacred story That many holy men and much more Virgins not to chuse Husbands for themselves 1 Cor. 7.36 Lib. 1. de Abrah c. ult women who by reason of their modesty and bashfulness ought especially in this case to be governed by others have in contracting Marriages submitted themselves to the authority of their Parents Non est virginalis pudoris eligere maritum It becomes not a Virgins modesty saith Ambrose † Grat. c. 32. q. 2. to chuse an Husband for her self And yet was not Esau's Marriage declared null nor his Children held as Illegitimate because in his Marriage he had not the consent of his Parent It is true That as to Daughters the chief power of disposing them is in the Father So in Euripides Hermione My Nuptial I to Parents care alone Commit for free choice therein have I none But as to Sons If we respect strict and Natural Right that of Quintilian will be found true That if it be lawful for a Son at any time to do things otherwise unreprovable without yea against his Fathers will surely that liberty is never more justifiable than in Marriage For as Cassiodore truly observes Durum est libertatem liberam non habere in Matrimonio Lib. 7. c. 4. unde liberi procreantur To be debarr'd of our free choice in Matrimony from whence our Children should be born is hard Ter. Andr. Act. 1. sc 5. nothing is more plain than that a Son in his Marriage should please himself XI It is a void Marriage that is contracted with anothers Wife or Husband That Marriage that is contracted with another mans Wife is doubtless null by the Law of Nature unless her former Husband have dismist her For so long doth his power last over her which by the Evangelical Law is not dissolved but by death The latter Marriage therefore is null for want of a moral power in the woman to dispose of her self which being lost by her former Marriage doth vitiate all those subsequent effects that attend it because every Act is but the invading of anothers Right So likewise on the other side by the same Law a Marriage contracted with the Husband of another Woman is alike void by reason of that power that Christ gives a chaste Wife over the body of her Husband XII Of Marriages between kindred Concerning Marriages between such as are nearly allied or of the same blood many difficult questions arise which are often with much zeal and animosity agitated on both sides Because he that shall undertake to assign certain and natural reasons why these Marriages that are by Law or Custome thus forbidden are unlawful should experimentally find how hard nay how impossible it is to effect it That alledged by Plutarch in his Roman Questions by St. Augustine in his Book De Civitate Dei by Philo in his Special Laws and by St. Chrysostome on 1 Cor. 13.13 as the contracting of new Friends and the strengthning our selves with new Alliances savours more of Policy than true Piety Nor are they of that force and energy as to conclude the contrary Acts to be either unlawful or void Whereunto may be added That some cases there may be wherein such prohibited Marriages may be more profitable and politick than others The Marriage of kindred sometimes profitable and politick as may be collected not only from that which God himself in his Law given to the Jews excepts of raising Seed to a deceased Brother having no issue But from that also of a Virgin left by her Father as sole heir of all his estate who by the Grecian and Hebrew Laws was to be Married to the next of kin to preserve the name and Estate in their own Tribe and Family and from many such like cases which do or may occur But yet from this general rule Incestuous Marriages forbid by the Law of Nature and why we must except the Marriages of Parents with their Children in what degree soever the reason whereof is sufficiently evident For neither can the Husband who by the Law of Matrimony is the head of the Wife pay that respect and reverence that Nature binds him to give to his Mother nor the Daughter to her Father For though she be subordinate to her Husband by Matrimonial Right yet doth her Marriage allow her so great a Familiarity with her Husband as is altogether inconsistent with the duty of a Child Paulus the Lawyer was in the right when having sa●d before That in contracting Marriages the Law of Nature and Modesty were chiefly to be regarded he added That it was against modesty for a man to take his own Daughter to be his Wife And Philo in his Special Laws condemns it as an execrable wickedness to pollute the bed of his deceased Father which as a thing Sacred ought not to be toucht and without regard to either the age or the reverence of a Mothers name to make himself both Son and Husband to the same Woman and to make her both Mother and Wife to the same Man Wherefore such Marriages are doubtless not illegal only but void by reason of something that is vicious which perpetually cleaves to the effects of it Neither is that Argument of Diogenes and Chrisippus which is drawn from the practice of Cocks and such like dumb creatures sufficient to prove that such commixtures are not repugnant to the Law of Nature That is unlawful which is repugnant to Humane Nature Lib. 2. Contr. J●●it For as I have already said it is enough to conclude any thing unlawful That it is repugnant though but to humane nature This is that Incest which the Lawyers Paulus and Papinian wrote to be by the Law of Nations committed between the degrees ascendent and descendent And this is that Law of Nature which as Xenophon notes is no less a Law because it was contemned by the Persians Medes Indians and Aethiopians for which they were punished with perpetual Wars Parricides Fratricides as Philo first and after him St. Hierome observed For as Michael Ephesius well interprets it That is Natural which is of common use amongst such Nations as are uncorrupted And that live most agreeable unto Nature And therefore Hippodamus the Pythagorean calls these incestuous commixtures inordinate and unnatural lusts unbridled passions and abominable pleasures Such were those of the Parthians whereof Lucan thus complains Epulis vesana meroque Regia non ullos exceptos legibus horret Concubitus With
mercy For that Divine Law that commanded them to destroy the Nations Deut. 7.4 Exod. 23.33 being compared with another charge given by God concerning them Deut. 20.10 will admit of this limitation That if they yielded upon the first summons they might be received to mercy As is clear by the Histories of Rahab who for securing the Spies was saved Jos 16.10 Of the Inhabitants of Gezer who were suffered to live among the Ephramites and to serve them Of the Gergezites of whom St. Matthew records Mat. 8.28 that there were some living even until his time Neither shall we find these ennumerated among those that were to have been extirpated as you may read Deut. 20.17 Jos 9.1 And lastly It is clear by that Act of Solomon 1 King 20.20 21 whereby he is said to have received the remainder of the Canaanites whom the Children of Israel could not destroy as his Tributaries and Bond-Servants unto that day Yea and if we examine the cause of that severe charge given unto Moses for their extirpation as it is exprest Exod. 23.33 Deut. 7.4 we shall find that in case as the Hebrew Doctors observed they would submit to the Commandments given to Noah and his Sons and pay Tribute the cause of their extirpation being taken away they might live Now why Joshua might not as well spare the Gibeonites upon their Dedition as he did Rahab and the Canaanites of Gezer upon theirs no solid Reason can be assigned And yet that the Gergezites being the Off-spring of the Inhabitants of Gezer were spared and lived as Tributaries to the Israelites till Christs time is most evident by the Sacred story The immediate cause of the destruction of all the rest of the Canaanites was not any inexorable Command given by God to Moses for that left them a possibility to live because a power to submit But the hardness of their hearts which proceeded from God as a punishment for all their great provocations Jos 11.19 20. that so he might destroy them utterly without any mercy as the Lord commanded Moses Wherefore considering that in case the Gibeonites had dealt plainly with Moses which they durst not do for fear of him and had voluntarily given themselves up as Bond-servants It is probable that he would have spared their lives under the same condition as he did the Inhabitants of Gezer Therefore Valuit juramentum The Oath was to remain inviolable Yea and the breach of this Oath three hundred years after when Saul either forgetting the Oath of his Forefathers or out of a well-meant zeal slew some of these Gibeonites cost the lives of many thousand Israelites 2 Sam. 21.6 in the three years Famine which God brought upon Israel Of this opinion was St. Ambrose who handling this Question saith Joshua did not think it safe to break the Peace with the Gibeonites because he had confirmed it by Oath Ne dum aliorum perfidiam arguit De Off. l. 3. c. 10. suam fidem solveret Lest whilest he punished others for their perfidiousness he should be found guilty of Perjury Neither did this fraud of theirs go altogether unpunished For whereas had they dealt plainly they had been admitted upon paying of Tribute only now their Corporal Slavery is at once the price of their lives and the just Punishment of their Craft and Subtilty So were the Brutiani served by the Romans Loh 10. c. 3. as Gellius relates V. The words of an Oath not to be too far extended Neither should the meaning of an Oath be wrested to any other sense than the words do usually bear Wherefore when the Children of Israel having sworn not to give their Daughters in Marriage to the Benjamites did notwithstanding suffer the Benjamites to take the Daughters of Shiloh by force and to enjoy them they were not guilty of Perjury For it is one thing to give and another not to require what is already lost Whereof St. Ambrose speaks thus This Indulgence of theirs was not without a Punishment suitable to their Intemperance whilest they were permitted only to enjoy those whom they had ravished without the solemnity of Marriage Nec hortabantur Israelitae nec prohibebant saith Joseph The Israelites did neither encourage the Benjamites nor forbid them Now the Law saith Seneca may punish him that succoureth an exile but not him that only suffers him to be relieved Not much unlike was that request which the Achaians made to the Romans who were highly displeased at some things by them done and confirmed by Oath namely That the Romans would be pleased to alter what they would but not to bind them by any Religious Vow to null those things which they had already established by Oath VI. Oaths bind not to things unlawful Secondly That an Oath be binding it is necessary that it refer to things lawful For if the thing promised upon Oath be forbidden either by the Law of Nature or by the Divine Law or interdicted by humane Laws whereof more anon it hath no power at all to oblige us That which is unlawful to be sworn is unlawful to be done being sworn and that which is unlawful for us to do is unlawful to be sworn All Oaths have a tacite exception of the higher powers and of former Oaths Now God is greater than man and therefore having first bound our selves unto him no Oath made against him or against our duty to him ought by us to be performed but repented of No Weapon formed against him shall prosper saith the Prophet Es 54. It is good counsel that Philo gives in this case Let him that goes about to do an unjust act by reason of his Oath know That he doth not thereby perform his Oath but break it For an Oath is a sacred thing which deserves our greatest care and devotion to preserve whereby we stand obliged to do such things only as are just and honest For he doth but accumulate one sin upon another who to a wicked Oath adds a dishonest action Wherefore let him that hath ensnared his own Soul by a rash Vow yet refrain from doing wickedly That God who is rich in mercy may forgive him For wilfully to contract a double guilt when we may be discharged from a single one is an incurable madness Rash Vows are ill made and sometimes worse kept Our Tongues must not bind our hands to do wickedly 1 Sam. 25. David was less sinful in breaking his Oath and sparing the life of Nabal whom he had sworn to kill than Herod was in killing the Baptist or Agamemnon in sacrificing Iphigenia for their Oaths sake Surely Oaths were never invented to be the Bonds of Iniquity Praestare fateor posse me tacitam fidem Si scelere careat interim scelus est fides My Faith perform I can I do confess If void of Sin else Faith's but Wickedness Some Promises cannot be performed saith Ambrose nor some Oaths kept without the violation of our duties to God or Man And if
as they are a Nation and all Kings as they are Kings should sympathize with their Neighbour Nations and Kings that are oppressed Neither is every person more bound to defend his own members than Princes are in obedience to Christ to defend each other with that power which he hath given them But this duty neither Kings nor People can well perform whilst Christendom is invaded by the Enemies of Christ unless they do mutually assist each other which can never be done successfully unless they strongly confederate together for that end And such a General League between Christian Princes hath heretofore been made whereof the Roman Emperor was by general consent chosen General whereby all Christians were obliged to contribute either Men or Mony according to their power as to the defence of Religion which is or ought to be the common cause for the neglect whereof I cannot see how any people can plead excuse unless it be such as are engaged in an inevitable War or afflicted with some other general calamity at home XIII If our Confederates are ingaged in several Wars which we ought to assist Another Question doth often arise namely in case two Nations are engaged in War one against the other and both are our Confederates whether of them we are bound to help Where in the first place we must remember what we have already said that ad Bella injusta nulla est obligatio No League can bind us to a War that is unjust He therefore is to be preferred that hath the juster cause if the War be against a stranger Prince yea if it be against another Confederate The words of him that swears Fealty to another are these Si scivero velle te aliquem juste offendere inde generaliter aut specialiter fuero requisitus meum tibi sicut potero praestabo auxilium If I shall understand See Book 3. chap. 25. §. 4. that thou wilt make an offensive War against any man upon a just ground and that I am either generally or specially required to give thee mine assistance I shall do it to my utmost power Thus Demosthenes in his Oration concerning Megalopolis The Athenians are bound by their League to aid the Messenians their Confederates against the Lacedaemonians their Confederates if the Lacedaemonians were the first Aggressors which holds true unless in our Articles it shall be expresly forbidden to send out any aid against such a Confederate Polyb. l. 6. In that Agreement which Hannibal made with the Macedonians there is this Clause Hostes erimus hostium exceptis Regibus Civitatibus c. Quibuscum foedus nobis amicitia est Enemies we shall be to thine Enemies except only such as are in League and Amity with us If two Nations be at War and both our Confederates and neither of them have a just cause which may so happen we are to stand Neuters and to assist neither So Aristides If either of our Confederates had required our aid against strangers it had been readily granted but if against one another we desire to stand Neuters Leuctrica If both our Confederates be engaged in a just War against strangers and both send for Aid if we are able we must send to both either Men or Money But if a Prince shall be required by both to aid them in his own person having so promised then because his person cannot be divided it is but reasonable that he should prefer him with whom he hath contracted the ancienter League As the Epirots answered the Lacedaemonians in Polybius The like answer was given to the Campanes by the Roman Consuls In contracting friends it is fit that we take care that the new do not supplant the old The Ancienter the Leagues are the more Inviolable Thus Ptolomy answered the Athenians in the like case Amicis ferenda Auxilia contra hostes non contra amicos We are to aid our Friends against Enemies but not against our Friends Which also will admit of this exception unless the latter League do bind us farther than our bare promise for it may include a translation of the Government and imply somewhat of subjection And thus we say that in selling of Goods the first sale is the best unless the latter shall also transfer the property and dominion So Livy of the Nepesines That the faith given upon their surrender bound them faster Deditionis quam societatis fides sanctior than that given by former Leagues as to their Associates Some there are that do more nicely distinguish between these But what I have said I take to draw nearest as to simplicity so also to truth XIV When renewed A League for a certain time prefixt is not easily presumed to be renewed through silence unless such acts intervene which cannot otherwise be understood for a new obligation is not easily to be presumed XV. The League is void if either party break it If either party violate the League the other party is freed because each Article of the League hath the force and vertue of a Condition Thus Thucydides determines it They saith he are not the first breakers of the League who being deserted seek for aid to others but they that perform not by their deeds what they have promised to do upon their Oaths And in another place Si vel tantillum ex dictis pars alterutra transgrederetur rupta sunt pacta If either party shall transgress the Articles they have sworn unto never so little the League is broken This also is true unless it be otherwise provided by the League as it usually is lest what is seriously debated and solemnly sworn should be adjudged to be broken upon every rash offence XVI How far Generals engaging are bound if the Prince refuse Sponsions are such promises or undertakings as Generals make without the consent of their Soveraign for the performance whereof they engage themselves or give hostages till it be confirmed by their Prince or Senate The subject matters whereof are as diverse as of Leagues They differ from Leagues in the dignity of those that make them Concerning these Engagements two Doubts usually arise The first is If the matter engaged for be refused by the King or State how far forth are the parties engaged bound Whether to make up what the King or State shall not think fit to grant or to restore all things to the same state and condition as they were in before such agreement was made or to deliver up their own bodies and the hostages to the Will of the Enemy The first whereof is most agreeable to the Civil Law of the Romans The second to Equity and Reason which we find urged by the Tribunes of the people in the Caudine Controversie The third is most approved of by Use and Custome as appears by the examples of the two notable Sponsions made at Caudis and Numantia But by no means may we admit The Sponsions made at Caudis and Numantia that either the King or
stripes and punishments as Gregory Bishop of Rome wrote unto the Bishop of Constantinople And we may read of many French Bishops who were by the judgement of the Church condemned for calling in the Civil Powers against the Priscillianists as Sulpitius Severus relates it and of a whole Council in the East that was condemned because they consented to the burning of Bogomilus It was therefore wisely said of Plato Errantis poena est doceri If there be any punishment due to errour it is to be instructed Sen Trag. Quis nomen unquam sceleris errori dedit Who ever thought it criminous to erre It is very true what Seneca saith De Ira. lib. 14. No wise man ever hated those that erred for if so he must necessarily sometimes hate himself He that is ignorant ought not to be ill treated nor accused but it is fit he should be instructed in that whereof he is ignorant Chrysost And Ammianus Marcellinus highly commends the Emperour Valentinian That he never persecuted any man for his Religion never commanded this or that to be adored nor inclined the hearts of his Subjects to enbrace his own manner of worship in case they dissented from it LI. But they that are openly impious and profane against such as they believe to be Gods may be punished Errours in Opinion concerning the nature or worship of God are not sufficient ground for a Just War but open impiety irreverence and profaneness towards any that is but acknowledged as God are deservedly in all Nations to be punished This amongst others is given as one Cause of the Peloponesian War between the Athenians and Lacedemonians and of that War which Philip of Macedon made against the Phocians whose sacriledge was so execrable that as Justine saith Lib. 8. Orbis viribus expiari debuit The whole world ought to have contributed to the expiation of it And it is St Hierom's observation upon the sixth of Daniel That whilst the vessels remained in the Idol Temple at Babylon the Lord was not angry Diod. lib. 16. for the errour was in the understanding and not in the will and affections though they erred in their Opinion concerning God yet were those vessels imployed to that use whereunto they were primarily consecrated but no sooner were they made use of in a common and profane way but the Lord breaks out into an open revenge St Augustine ascribes the prosperity of the Roman Empire to their care of Religion though a false one And Lactantius seems to justifie them in part because they had a Zeal for the Worship of God though not according to knowledge though they could not exactly perform their duty yet they served him sincerely according to the light they had of him And as we said before by what God soever we forswear the sin is punished by the True God because we swear by it as God De benef 7. c. 7. saith Seneca And it is our opinion of him that we swear by that obligeth the True God to revenge it De benef lib. 3. c. 6. And in this sense we understand that also of Seneca The punishments of such as profane Religion may vary but in all places they are punishable And that also of Plato De legib 10. who would have all such as scoff at Religion punished with death In like manner they that falsely assume unto themselves the name of Prophets are deservedly to be punished as Agathias testifies Lib. 5. CHAP. XXI Of the Communication of Punishments I. How punishments may pass to those that partake of the sin II. That Commonalties and their Governours are punishable for the Subjects faults if they know of them and do not hinder them when they both ought and may do it III. Likewise by receiving those who have been criminous elsewhere IV. Vnless they either punish them or deliver them up to be punished illustrated by examples V. The Rights of Suppliants belong to the unfortunate and not to the guilty with its exceptions VI. Suppliants are to be defended till their Cause be known and by what Law this knowledge is to be gained VII How Subjects may partake of the faults of their Rulers or the Members of the whole Body and how their punishments differ VIII How long the Right of punishing may continue against a People IX Whether a punishment may be inflicted upon such as partake not of the faults X. A distinction between that punishment that is inflicted directly and that which comes by consequence XI That which comes by occasion of a fault distinguish'd from that which is inflicted for the fault XII Properly no man can be justly punished for the fault of another XIII No not the Children for the sins of their Parents XIV Objections answered concerning Gods Dealings with the Children of guilty Parents XV. Much less should their punishments extend to their other Relations XVI Yet some things may be denied unto these which otherwise they might have with examples XVII Neither can Subjects be properly punished for the defaults of their Kings XVIII Nor the dissenting part for the crimes of the major part XIX The Heir is not liable to the punishment of his Ancestor as it is a punishment and why XX. Yet he shall if what was first inflicted as a punishment do pass under another kind of debt I. How by partaking of the sin of another man we may be liable to his punishment SO often as mention is made concerning the Communication of Punishments either it concerns those that are Partakers of the sin or some others They that partake of the sin are not so properly punished for other mens sins as their own And who they are that partake of other mens sins may easily be understood by what hath been already said above concerning the damage that is occasioned by an injury done For by the same ways almost whereby a man is made guilty of that damage by the same may a man be made guilty of another mans sin and yet not always where there is an obligation to satisfie for the damage there is the same to satisfie for the offence but there only where there is the concurrence of some notable malignity whereas oft-times any offence may suffice to oblige a man to satisfie for the damage given He therefore that commands a wicked act to be done as David did Joab concerning Vriah he that gives his consent being required as Saul is said to stone St Steven because he gave his consent unto it for by the Law Facientem consentientem par poena constringit The same punishment is due to him that commits a crime and to him that consents to the committing of it They that aid and assist in the act doing they that receive or conceal the matter or any other way participate of the crime so St Hierome Not only the Thief himself Sup. Parabolas but he that knowing the thing to be stoln and where it is conceals it or
their power All which arising from natural equity may by a parity of reason be applied to Princes and their Subjects wherefore Proclus upon that of Hesiod Whole Cities sometimes smart for th' crimes of one assigns this as the reason Because having power they did not restrain him from his wickedness So in the Grecian Army Agamemnon and some others being subject to a General Council of war It was deservedly said The Princes errours on their Subjects fall That is the Grecians were plagued for the folly of their Princes because it was in the power of that Council to have compelled Agamemnon and the rest to have delivered up Iphigenia to the Priest to have been sacrificed Thus doth Cyrillus expound this matter in his Fifth Book against Julian whereupon Ovid thus Virgine raptâ Met. l. 14. Quam meruit poenam solus digessit in omnes The Virgin gone All stand engag'd though done by one alone Because it was in their power to have hindered it Thus doth St. Chrysostome involve all the inhabitants of Antioch in the crimes of the Statues De Statuis orat 1. The fact saith he though committed but by few we all stand accused of and the revenge which is strictly due unto those only that did it is threatned against us all which we might have avoided had we before expelled them the City So might we by a timely cutting off from us those parts that were exulcerated have wisely provided for the safety of the whole And a little after For this very thing thou art punished and utterly destroyed because thou wert not present to resist because thou didst not prohibit because thou didst not restrain their madness that thou didst not expose thy self to danger to preserve the honour of the Emperour 't is true thou didst not join with them nor partake of their crime in this I commend thee this I take in good part but because thou didst not hinder them that did it for this thou art worthily accused Livy records that as a good plea which the Vejentes and the Latines made before the Roman Senate namely That their Subjects had aided their Enemies without their knowledge But on the contrary it was not allowed unto Teuca Queen of the Illyrians when she pleaded that they were her Subjects and not her self that were the Pirates for she knew thereof and forbad them not for it might easily be presumed That of what was so frequently and so publickly done no Prince could plead ignorance The Laurentine Embassadors being assaulted by some of King Tatius his near relations did complain that the Law of Nations was violated but Tatius favouring his own kindred more than common right drew the revenge wholly upon himself And hitherto may that of Salvian be properly applyed That Sovereign Princes who are able to prohibit the greatest crimes do seem to approve of them if they permit them to be done It is sufficient for private men to keep themselves upright but they that are Princes must take care that others offend not Dion in Galba can 4. Synod Pistensis Non est liber à consensu qui quod emendare potest emendare negligit He that neglects his duty in reforming abuses doth without doubt consent if not approve of them and thereby involves himself both in the sin and punishment Id quod à multis fit necesse est ut à nemine ignoretur Dion Prusaeensit what is done by a multitude no man can be ignorant of Polybius reproves the Aetoleans sharply because when they would not appear to be enemies to Philip yet they suffered their subjects openly to act against him in an hostile manner yea and preferred the principal actors to great Honours III. Of receiving Malefactors into protection Hitherto we have shewed how they that preside over others may be involved in their sins and punishments by toleration now let us see how they may partake of their punishment by reception against punishments although by the Law of nature every innocent person hath a right to punish a Malefactor yet since the institution of civil societies it is generally agreed That all each particular mans crimes that shall be committed properly against that society should be left to them and to their Governours either to punish or absolve as themselves shall please yet is not this Right so absolute and full as to those offences which do any way appertain to humane society but that other Cities and their Governours may have the like power to prosecute them in the same manner as for some offences Popular actions are usually granted in every City much less have they that full power in such offences whereby any City or its Governour is peculiarly wronged but that that City or Governour hath likewise a right either for the vindication of his own honour or for his future security either to require the offender to be delivered up unto him or to require that he be punished by that City wherein he lives according to the injuries he hath suffered by him and of this right he is not to be deprived IV Who ought to be either punished or delivered up Seeing that it is neither usual nor safe for one Prince to permit another to enter into his Dominions with an Army to demand Delinquents to just punishment therefore it is fit that the injured Prince should send to him under whose protection the Malefactor resides to require that either he would punish him himself according to his merits or to deliver him up to the pleasure of the Prince that is injured and this is that dedition whereof we find so frequent mention in all Histories Thus did the rest of the Tribes require the Benjamites to deliver up those Sons of Belial that had abused the Levites Concubine Judg. 20. and the Philistines Sampson Jud. 15. Paus l. 14. Thus did the Lacedemonians make War upon the Messenians for refusing to deliver up a man that had killed divers Lacedemonians And at another time Strabo l. 8. for not delivering up those that had ravished some virgins that were sent to perform their devotions So Cato would have had the Senate to have delivered up Caesar for the War he unjustly made upon the Germans Plut. vit Camilli And the Gauls did in the like manner require the Fabii to be delivered up unto them who had made war against them unjustly Thus did the Romans demand from the Carthaginians That Amilcar who had solicited the Gauls to Rebelion Livy lib. 28. should be delivered and afterwards Hannibal as Diodorus and Livy testifie Thus likewise they required Jugurtha of Bocchus in these words So shalt thou at once free us from the necessity of persecuting thee for thine errour and him for his wickedness Salust Thus the Achaians required from the Lacedemonians those who had besieged Lanvicus adding that unless they did deliver them they would declare that they had broken the League And thus did the Athenians make publick
of the Law do not observe it although haply that Law be promulgated and time of it self sufficient allowed for the knowledge thereof As also in such as go to Law both Parties may be free not from injustice only Nemo debet jus suum indiscussum relinquere Tentanda sunt quaecunque tantum sunt Baldus but from any thing else that is blameable especially when both or either of them contend not in the behalf of themselves but of others as a Tutor for his Pupil a Guardian for his Ward whose Right he is bound in duty to defend though that Right be but uncertain So in a wager at Law two persons may contend for one and the same thing and yet neither of them be unjust So also a Councellor may plead for either of them without the least derogation to his honesty Again when something that is very profitable stands in opposition to what is honest it is no easie matter to tell whether of them to follow When we first entred into War with Niger saith Severus the Emperour there was I confess no very plausible pretence for War but the Empire lay at stake between us and both of us strove which should appropriate it to himself Herodian Nay as Aristotle well notes to say of a Judge that he judgeth right is but an Ambiguous speech for it may signifie either that he judgeth 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 plainly as he ought without any ignorance or 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 according to the best of his knowledge or the clearest evidence that is brought before him And therefore the sentence which must pass according to that evidence may be through mis-information unjust and yet the Judge that passeth that sentence may be righteous * Si dubium sit à qua parte stet justitia hanc si utraque pars quaerit injusta esse neutra possit If it be doubtful on what side the Right stands if both Parties contend for it it is probable that neither doth unjustly The Jews made War against the Canaanites justly being so commanded by God and the Canaanites being ignorant of that charge given against them did justly in defending themselves wherefore that War was on both sides just Thus Pope Pius the second answered the Hungarian Embassador that complained against the Emperour namely He thought that the King of Hungary did intend nothing dishonestly and he knew that the Emperour was a great lover of justice But both contending for the Kingdom probable it was that neither of them thought his Cause unjust In disceptationibus fori par est litigantis utriusque jus donec lata est pro altero eorum sententia In all controversies this is found true but especially in War that both Parties pretend to maintain a Cause that is just But in War it is hardly possible that either party should be in that sense just that is free from all blame by reason of that great defect of love and that overmuch rashness that for the most part inseparably accompanies it besides the weightiness of the business it self which is such as being not satisfied with probabilities strictly requires such proofs as are demonstrative and convincing But if we account that to be just which is permitted to enjoy some effects of Right it is most certain According to the effects of right War may be on both sides just that War in this sense may be on both sides just as will appear anon when we come to treat of a publick solemn War for so both a sentence though not rightly past and a possession not rightly gained have both of them some effects of that which is right CHAP. XXIV War though Just not to be undertaken rashly I. It it better sometimes to remit our own Right than to engage in a doubtfull War II. But especially when undertaken to exact punishment III. And chiefly by a King that is injured IV. And that sometimes for his own and his Subjects safety V. Certain Rules guiding us to a prudent choice of things apparently good VI. An example whereby we may be guided in our endeavours after liberty or peace whereby the miseries of War may be prevented VII Punishment not to be exacted by War unless by the most potent party VIII War not to be undertaken unless compelled by necessity IX Or when we have some very great Cause together with some notable advantage X. The miseries of War lively described I. Better sometimes to forego our right than to make War for it THough it be not properly pertinent to our purpose in treating only of the Rights of War to shew how far other Virtues do either enjoyn or perswade thereunto yet will it not be altogether impertinent for preventing of mistakes to give some cautions about it lest any man should think that whensoever he hath a Just Cause offered him he is bound to make War or at least that it is at all times lawfull for him so to do whereas on the contrary it is for the most part much more pious to remit somewhat of our Right than to endeavour to defend it by a dangerous War We Christians are especially taught to expose our own lives to the greatest perils that can be to preserve the lives and as much as in us lies to procure the everlasting welfare of others in imitation of our great Lord and Master who laid down his own life to save ours even then when we were strangers nay enemies unto him Rom. 5.6 How much more reason have we to forbear the prosecution of our Just Rights when they cannot be obtained without the effusion of so much Christian blood and the destruction of so many mens Lives and Estates Pol. lib. 4. Rhet. ad Alex. c. 3. besides other mischiefs which War usually brings with it This we are forewarn'd of by Aristotle and also by Polybius not for every such cause to run the hazard of a War For the necessary defence of our Liberties our Wives and Children we may lawfully make War saith Gallio in Seneca but not for such things as are either superfluous or being lost Suasoria 5. Philostratus lib. 23. do not much damnifie us This and somewhat more did Apollonius say to the King of Babylon We are not to contend with the Romans for a few small Villages which many of our Ancestors being but private men did enjoy They must be great matters indeed that should so far provoke us Adv. Apion de popul suis as to undertake a War especially with such potent enemies The like Josephus testifies of his Countrey men It is not our custom to muster up our Forces or to make War to enlarge our Dominions but for the defence of our Laws All other losses we can bear with patience but being debar'd the use of our Religion we undertake War beyond our strength and prosecute them to the utmost of dangers It was prudently advised by Dion Prusaeensis in his Oration concerning War and Peace We are
to be lamented whosoever therefore shall with any remorse consider those so great so horrid and so direful effects of War cannot but confess that it is miserable but he that can feel them or think upon them without sorrow much more he that can glory in the success of them Ideo se putat beatum quia humanum perdidit sensum Therefore thinks himself happy because he hath lost all sentiments of humanity So the same Father in another place tells us that Id de Civit Dei lib. 4. c. 15. Belligerare malis videtur felicitas bonis necessitas Good men make War their refuge but wicked men make it their delight And were there nothing of injustice in the War yet to be enforced unto it that is in it self miserable saith Maximus Tyrius whereunto he adds Wise men never make War but by constraint whereas fools fight for pleasure and gain Lib. 13. The Lacedemonians in Diodorus considering those great enmities and animosities likely to arise from War thought themselves bound in duty to declare before the Gods and unto all good men that they were not the Authors of it Plutarch brings in some making this objection But hath not Rome much improved her self by War Whereunto he answers 'T is true indeed she hath so in the opinion of those who place their greatest glory in Riches in Pleasure Wantonness and Martial Power which are but the dregs of Honour but not in theirs who place their glory in the safety of their People in meekness justice and contentation It was therefore worthily said of Stephanus the Phiysician unto Cosroes King of Persia To thee O King who art wholly conversant in blood and slaughter in subduing Kingdoms and depopulation Cities other glorious attributes may be due but surely thou canst never hope by these ways to be esteemed good for as no good man will greedily covet that which is anothers so Non est homini homine prodigè utendum as Seneca tells us Aelian lib. 14. c. 2. It is no point of Honour to be prodigal of humane Blood Philiscus advised Alexander to be emulous of Glory but not by making himself like unto a Plague in depopulating Cities and laying whole Kingdoms wast Nothing can add more Glory to a King than to provide for the safety of his Subjects that they may live in Peace Nat. Hist l. 7. c. 25. Pliny after he had recounted so many famous Battels gained by the Dictator C. Caesar wherein were slain as he there computes Eleven hundred Ninety two thousand men adds this I do not reckon it as any part of his Glory to have done so great wrong to mankind however provoked Philo in the life of Moses observes That though the killing of Enemies in War were by the Laws permitted yet whosoever did kill a man though justly though in his own defence though compelled thereunto against his will did notwithstanding contract some guilt unto himself in respect of that common kindred and alliance between man and man which was derived from the supreme Cause wherefore expiations and purgations were thought necessary to cleanse them from that crime which seemed to be committed by them If then by the Hebrew Laws He that killed a man though against his will Pollutus esset hostili quidem attamen sanguine was to betake himself to one of the Cities of refuge And if God would not permit David to build him a Temple because he was a man of blood though of his enemies that is as Josephus writes because he had made many Wars which by the Law was permitted If among the Ancient Greeks he that had slain a man though accidentally Lib. 7. cap. 4. or in defence of himself had need of expiation Who cannot see how unhappy a thing it is and by all means to be avoided voluntarily to engage our selves in a War though haply not unjust Surely among the Greek Churches that most Christian Canon was long in force whereby he that in what War soever had slain a man though an enemy was not by the space of three years admitted unto the Sacrament CHAP. XXV For what Causes a War may be undertaken for others I. That a War may justly be undertaken by a Prince for his Subjects II. But yet it is not always to be so undertaken III. Whether an innocent Subject may be delivered up to an enemy to prevent a War IV. That a War may justly be undertaken in the behalf of our Confederates equal or unequal V. As also for our Friends VI. Yea and for any man VII Yet may it also be omitted without blame if it endanger himself or cannot be done without the death of the invader VIII Whether that War be just that is made to relieve another mans Subjects this explained by a distinction IX All those military consociations and mercenary succours that respect not the equity of the Cause are unjust X. To engage in War for spoil or pay only is wicked I. A Prince may justly make War for his Subjects ABove when we treated of such persons as had a Right to make War it was said and shewed That naturally every man had a power to vindicate not only his own but the right of another † See lib. 1. c. 5. wherefore look what Causes do justifie a War undertaken for our selves the very same do justifie a War made for another But our principal and most necessary care should be for our own Subjects whether they be our Domesticks or such as live under our Civil Government for they are a part of the Governour as we there shewed Josh 10.6 Persicor 2. Thus Joshua we read made War in defence of the Gibeonites who had yielded themselves unto him It is not sufficient to denominate a Man Just that he wrongs no man saith Procopius unless he also be carefull to protect those from injuries who for that very end have put themselves under him Our Ancestors saith Cicero to the Roman Senate did often make Wars in the behalf of their Merchants and Mariners when they have been abused by Strangers Verr. 2. And in another place How many Wars saith he did our forefathers undertake to revenge the wrongs done to the Citizens of Rome when their Seamen have been imprisoned and their Merchants spoiled Yea and the very same Romans who refused to take Arms in the defence of a People that were their Confederates thought it necessary to defend the same People when they had surrendred themselves and so became their Subjects Thus do the Campanes bespeak the Romans Though ye refused to assist or defend us against our enemies whilst we were your Friends and Confederates yet now that we are your Subjects you will certainly protect us Whereupon Florus saith That the Campanes made that League which they had formerly contracted with the Romans more strong and inviolable by their voluntary surrender of all they had unto them for it agreed not with the Faith of the Romans
Livy lib. 7. saith Livy to desert such II. Yet is it not alwayes convenient Neither is it prudence in a Governour to enter into a War always though upon a just ground for any particular Subject unless it may be done safely without endangering all or the greatest part of his Subjects For it is the Duty of a good Prince to prefer the safety of the whole before its parts and the greater the part is that he provideth for the nearer it draws to the nature of the whole III. Whether an innocent Subject may be delivered up to preserve the whole Wherefore in case the Enemy shall require any one person to be delivered to death though that person be innocent there is no question but that he may be forsaken if it clearly appear that the City is too weak to make resistance For as Nicephorus in Zonaras advised rightly concerning the delivering up of the Fugitives to the Bulgarian General to purchase their peace We judge it much better that a few men should perish than that so great a multitude should be destroyed Non malo unius domus Commune vinci sed nec aequari potest No one mans sufferings can equal be Unto a general calamitie When Alexander had destroyed Thebes he came to Athens threatning to destroy it Plut. vit Phocion unless Demosthenes Lycurgus and others who had highly exasperated the people against him were delivered vnto him Phocion thereupon being urged in the Senate to deliver his Opinion in that Case pointing to his dear friend Nicocles answered Eo in fortunii urbem nostram isti perduxerunt ut etiamsi hunc Nicoclem meum dedi Alexander poscat dedi jussurus sum Into such a desperate condition have these men brought this City that if Alexander had demanded my dearest friend Nicocles my Vote should have past for his delivery Yea and I should think my self happy might my life alone be accepted as a sacrifice to preserve it It is true Vasquius seems to be of a contrary judgment yet he that throughly weighs not so much his words as his intention and purpose may perceive that all he aims at is this only That such an innocent person is not rashly or easily to be delivered where there remains any hopes that he may be defended For he there brings in a story of a certain Band of Italian Foot whom he deservedly condemns for deserting Pompey before his Case was desperate upon Caesar's promise of safety and protection which he condemns and that not unworthily But whether an innocent Citizen may be delivered up into the enemies power to preserve his City from imminent ruine is much disputed now amongst the learned as it formerly was when Demosthenes invented that notable Apologue of the Wolves who were content to make peace with the sheep upon condition that their Dogs might be delivered up unto them Neither doth Vasquius only deny this but Sotus also whose Opinion Vasquius condemns as being too near a neighbour to treachery Yet Sotus was of Opinion that such a Citizen ought to deliver up himself which Vasquius denies being swayed by this reason because the nature of a Civil Society which was at the first entred into for mutual preservation doth not permit it But the force of this argument reacheth no farther than this That no Citizen is bound so to do by any right strictly taken but it argues not That if he do it he transgresseth the rules of Charity For there are many Duties which though not by the strict rules of Justice yet by the bonds of Charity we stand obliged to perform which are not only laudable being done as Vasquius acknowledgeth but which cannot be left undone without blame whereof this is one That every man prefers the safety of an innocent multitude before his own Know ye not saith Caiaphas the High Priest that it is better that is less evil that one man should die than that the whole Nation should perish For the destruction of no one Family can equal the destruction of the Universe A particular mischief is much more tolerable than a general calamity And therefore Phocion did wisely when he perswaded Demosthenes rather to undergo death himself than that for him his Native Countrey should be destroyed Diodor. lib. 17 which he urged upon him by the examples of the Daughters of Leus and of the Hyacinthides This was Cicero's resolution in the like case as appears by that Oration he made for P. Sextius If it should happen saith he that sailing in a ship with my friends and being therein assaulted by many Pyrats who peremptorily resolved to sink the ship unless I only were delivered up unto them I should chuse rather to cast my self into the sea to preserve my friends than endeavour to preserve mine own life with the danger of theirs And so in another place An honest and a prudent man observing the Laws and knowing the duties of a Civil Life De finib lib. 3. doth always prefer a general good before the advantage of any particular person though of himself Livy speaking of certain Molossians saith That he had often heard of men that willingly exposed themselves to death for the defence of their Countrey But these saith he are the first that ever I heard of that thought it fit that their Countrey should perish for themselves only But here also it may be questioned whether a Citizen though obliged in duty to do it may be compelled thereunto This Sotus denies by the example of a rich man that is bound by the bonds of mercy and charity to administer to the necessities of the poor yet cannot be compelled thereunto But we must here note that there is not the same reason for the parts compared between themselves as there is for the Superiors compared with those that are subject unto them for equals cannot compel one another unless it be to such things as are strictly due whereas it is in the power of Superiors as Superiors to enforce their inferiors to any virtuous act for the publick good So we read that the Lucans ordained a punishment against Prodigality the Macedonians against Ingratitude and the Athenians and Lucans both against Idleness As in a time of dearth any one Citizen may be enforced to produce his private store of Grain and to make it publick So in this case whatsoever Charity requires of us the Magistrate for a more universal good hath a power to enforce as Phocion would have delivered up his friend Nicocles had Alexander demanded him IV. War may justly be made for our confederates equal or unequal Next unto our own Subjects or rather equally to be defended are our Confederates whether they surrender themselves upon condition of protection or whether it be covenanted for mutual aid and assistance Qui non repellit injuriam à socio si potest tam est in vitio quam ille qui facit He that defends not his Associate when it is in his power is as
thought worthy to be observed Yet should goodness and common humanity prevail with all men but especially Christians to pass by small faults but chiefly if repented of For as the Poet speaks Quem poenitet peccâsse pene est innocens He 's almost guiltless who is penitent But yet to the end that the Peace may be the better preserved Yet small offences are to be referred to these of smaller concernment this Clause ought be added That in case any of them should be broken it should not amount so high as to the breach of the peace But that such things should be first put to reference before it should be lawful to take Arms which we find added to the Peloponnesian League recorded by Thucydides XXXVI Or some punishment for them inflicted And I am clear of opinion that the same may be done in case some special punishment be inserted in those Articles not that I am ignorant that such an agreement there may be That it shall be in the choice of the Party injured either to accept of some punishment or to null the Peace But that the nature of the offence may be such as requires rather that Lib. 3. c. 19. §. 14. than this Besides what I have formerly said and proved by the Authority of History is evident That he that fulfils not his promise being first failed breaks not the Peace for he is not bound but under condition XXXVII What if hindered by necessity But if the nonperformance of what is agreed unto be occasioned through necessity as if the thing promised be taken away or perished or if what was agreed to have been done be by any chance or casualty rendred impossible the Peace shall not be deemed as broken For as we have said before Peace doth not usually depend on such conditions as are casual But the other Party shall be at his choice whether he had rather expect the performance of that promise hereafter if there remain any hopes that it may be done though late or receive to the value of the thing promised or lastly whether he had rather be discharged from some other thing mutually promised and answerable to that in this Article and that is thought equivalent to it XXXVIII Yet if the innocent party will the Peace is not broken It is certainly an argument of great integrity in the innocent party to preserve the Peace even with those who have often broken their Faith as Scipio did with the Carthaginians notwithstanding their many perfidious dealings with them because no man can possibly cancel his obligation by doing contrary unto it For although it be exprest that by such a contrary fact the Peace shall be broken yet is this so to be understood that it shall ly in the choice of the innocent person whether he will make such an advantage thereof or not XXXIX The third way of breaking Peace Lastly we said That the Peace may be broken by doing that which is contrary to the special nature of every Peace XL. What falls under the notion of Friendship Thus those things that are done contrary to Friendship do break that Peace that was contracted under condition of Friendship for look what the duty of friendship may require from others ought also to be performed by the Right of this agreement And to this though not to every Peace for some there are that are not tyed up to this condition Pro Gabin as Pomponius observes may we refer many of those dissertations which Civilians handle concerning such injuries and contumelies as are committed without force of Armes and particularly that of Tully If after Peace made any thing be committed it shall not be accounted as a bare neglect but as a wilful breach neither shall it be imputed to impudence but unto perfidiousness And even here also as much as in us lies we are to take care that we judge not of the fact invidiously if therefore an injury be done against either our Allies or Subjects it shall not be imputed to him with whom we have made Peace unless it be evident that it was done by his instigation According to which natural equity do the Roman Laws proceed concerning such acts of cruelty as are done against Servants as Adultery and Ravishment are imputed rather to acts of unbridled lust than of hatred and so the invading of another mans Right is adjudged as an act of Covetousness rather than of Treachery Cruel threatnings whether by words or signs unless it be upon some new cause given cannot consist with friendship no more than can the erecting of new Forts and Bulwarks upon the Frontiers when it is manifest that they are not so much for defence as offence so also the more than ordinary preparations for War either by Sea or Land if he with whom the Peace is made have ground enough to believe that they are made against none but against himself XLI To receive Exiles whether contrary to friendship The reception of such particular persons as are willing to transplant themselves from one Princes Dominions to another is no breach of Friendship for this freedom is not only natural but benign whereunto we may likewise add the receiving of Exiles for as I have elsewhere proved out of Euripides * Lib. 2. c. 5. §. 24. over such the City or Prince that banished them can have no power What advantage is it saith Perseus in Livy † Lib. 42. that every man hath power to banish himself if there be no place left him to fly unto And this Aristides calls a right common to all mankind to receive persons banished * Leuctr 2. Solon would not admit that any Strangers should be enrolled among his Citizens but such as had been for ever banished their own Country or such as came with their whole Families to Athens there to exercise some Craft or Manufacture Perseus in Appian pleads thus with the Romans concerning his receiving of some fugitives What I did saith he was justifiable by the common right of all mankind which you your selves also do sometimes which likewise is usually confirmed by mutual Covenants as may appear by that Peace made between the Romans and the Persians The like doth Strabo testifie of the Aradii who whilst the Kings of Syria were at War among themselves obtained this liberty That they might receive what Fugitives they pleased but send away none But as to walled Towns or any great Multitudes that did constitute any one entire part of a City that it is not lawful for any Prince to receive these we have already proved This was the cause of the War between the Persians and the Romans Lib. 2. c. 5. §. 24. because King Lazus at the sollicitation of the Consul had revolted to the Romans Neither is it lawful to receive such as are bound either by Oath or otherwise to perform duty or service to another Prince The like hath sometimes been introduced by the Law of Nations among some people
236. under Alexander deny to carry Materials to the Temple of Belus 428. in what Cases not to associate with wicked Kings page 185 Ignorance excuses when page 237 Ignorants to be spared in a Just War page 500 Ignorantly and through Ignorance distinguished ibid. Islands and Increments by inundation whose 136. floating 137. how distinguished from Increments ibid. Images abhorred by the Persian Magi 466. to deface to him that believes to include a Deity impiety ibid. Imperare 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 〈◊〉 page 50 Impiety and open profaneness towards any that is acknowledged as God punishable page 392 Imprisonment unjust to what it obligeth page 201 Importation of some goods prohibited page 86 Of Inequality The Law of Nation takes no cognizance if consented unto page 165 Incestuous Marriages forbidden by the Law of Nature 107. two reasons given against such page 109 An Increment what is thereby meant 138. whether stopt by an Highway 139. it is his whos 's the River is o● his whos 's the Grounds are that bound it 138. it is his to whom the Land is granted if the Land be arcifinious ibid. if in doubts is the peoples ibid. whether it may belong to the Princes Vassal ibid. Indians many Wives 106. no Tribunals but for murder and injuries done page 211 Induciae whence page 558 Infants capable of Dominion 89. but not to dispose thereof without a Guardian ibid. so is he to inherit but not to dispose of it page 103 Infeudations 119. made by Kings without the peoples consent void with consent how gained ibid. Ingratitude of the Romans punished by M. Levinus with disfranchizement page 39 To Inhabit any Country free for Exiles page 85 Injuries faults mischances distinguished 500 on the one side makes War just on the other 70. what oblige to restitution what not page 531 Injure others we ought not to benefit our selves page 82 Injuries done us by our Country Prince Parents to be patiently born page 58 Injuries intended only sometimes punished page 383 Innocents to be defended page 425 426 The Innocent not to be destroyed with the Nocent page 504 The Innocent falshood of Joseph to his Brethren page 443 Instruments of the Plough not to be taken in pawn page 514 To Insult over the Vanquished ignoble page 506 507 Intent sometimes equally punished with the fact 381. though ill obligeth not to restitution page 383 Invaders Command how far obliging 62. in what Case he may be killed by a private man page 65 For the Interpretation of Promises and Contracts some Rules page 193 What Interpretations given to contracts between Enemies 558. if odious in their full propriety if ambiguous in the largest sense page 193 Interpretation of Leagues 190 sometimes gathered from the Context 191 192. if in doubt ought to favour the weakest page 548 Intestates Estate to whom naturally it descends page 122 Invasion made by Confederates or their Subjects whether it break the Peace 548. by Subjects when attributed to the Prince ibid. By Inundation the Owner may lose his Right page 137 Inundations and Increments thereby gained page 136 137 Josephus in expounding the Hebrew Law flatters the Romans page 466 To Judge of the Cause of a War between Princes dangerous page 457 The Judges Office in criminal Causes dangerous page 373 A Judge should be tenderly affected as a Father 416 417. may be punished his Sentence being unjust but not the Executioner 429. said to be just though the Sentence be unjust page 55 In Judgment the matter not the Persons to be considered page 3 4 To Judge of a mans meaning by his speech how due page 441 Judgment of zeal what page 445 Judgment contemplative and practical page 429 Judging of the Supreme Power Ca●tions page 41 The Judgment how steered in doubtful Cases page 411 Against Judgment though erroneous nothing to be done ibid. Judgments Capital why by Christ permitted 372 373. Christians may execute them but not affectedly ibid. Jus and Justice how distinguish'd page 494 Just in War what page 2 Just taken strictly what page 414 Justice derived from Jove Pref. vi Justice and Valour usually attended by Victory xii Justice Expletive and Attributive page 4 Just Cause procures Friends xii Just Cause adds courage to Souldiers ibid. Justice Commutative or Expletive page 3 Justice how described by Porphyry v. preferred to fortitude x. it begets courage 430. it so gives to every one his own that it detracts not from the just Right of another 198. it should extend it self to all Mankind x Where Justice is not required the longest Sword takes all page 435 K. KEturah's Son by Abraham received Gifts or Portions but no Inheritances page 125 He that Kills an Enemy in the War is guiltless page 357 To Kill a man for slight injuries is againast Charity 73. in defence of our Goods naturally not unlawful page 74 To Kill a private man is murder but thousands in an unjust War Valour and Vertue page 70 To Kill a Nocturnal Thief whether tolerated only by the Civil Law or approved 75 76. an incorrigible Malefactor not against the Law of Nature page 368 To Kill an Enemy after Battel against Charity page 506 To Kill an Enemy privately in his own Quarters whether lawful page 462 To be Killed none for his valour in defence of his own cause if good page 568 To Kill all that have offended brutish page 501 Who may be justly Killed in a just War according to Justice internal page 498 Kings Grants when revocable and when not 180. their Contracts do not always bind their Successors page 178 179 Kings how they serve God as Kings page 17 18 Kings whether bound by prescription see Prescription Kings that make Laws not subject to Laws 377. not all constituted by the People 40. not bound by their own Laws directly 101. in name some not in power 39. whether he may renounce his Kingdom so as his Son shall not inherit page 131 Kings raised by providence fit for the times and People 41. they have no superiour but God 40. their vices must be born with patience ibid. to revile them is wicked but to kill them though wicked horrid page 39 A Kings person to be spared in cases of absolute necessity page 66 Kings regard honour more than power yet doth not this abate of their Right 54. their private Acts subject to the Laws page 177 Against Kings the Law that makes void any private mans Acts by way of Punishment is void ibid. Kings Promises Contracts and Oaths page 176 A Kings word as firm as an Oath page 175 A King may null his own Oath as private men antecedenter not consequenter 177. whether he may revoke his own acts which he doth as a King page 176 Kings defended by severe Laws page 61 By the Contract of a King how the Heir may be bound page 178 How a King may be bound to his Subjects naturally and how civilly page 177 Kings bound by their own Laws as a member not as the body